Definition of sin as acquiescence to filth

This is my conversation with my Thomas Aquinas Emulator based on ChatGPT.

We undertake to define sin in everyday common-sense language without any religious or philosophical influences. He likes my idea very much. In fact, he is willing to adopt my terminology.


Defining Sin in Common-Language

February 14, 2024

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
I want to undertake the philosophical project of defining sin so that a number of conditions are satisfied. Firstly, it is compatible with your own notion. Secondly, it is framed in everyday common-sense language without any religious or philosophical influences. It is meant as a starting position for dialogue between exponents of various epistemological positions concerning religion. Do you understand the purpose of the project?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Question 1: The suitability of undertaking a philosophical project to define sin, ensuring compatibility with Aquinas's notion and framing it in common-sense language for interdisciplinary dialogue?

Article 1. Whether it is possible to define sin in a manner that is both compatible with Aquinas's understanding and expressed in common-sense language?

Objection 1. It seems impossible to define sin in a manner compatible with my understanding while simultaneously employing only everyday common-sense language. My conceptualization of sin is deeply embedded in theological and philosophical frameworks, which rely on specific religious and metaphysical presuppositions. Extracting sin from this context might strip the concept of its nuanced meaning, rendering any definition incompatible.

Objection 2. Furthermore, considering the diverse and complex nature of epistemological positions concerning religion, any attempt to frame sin in strictly common-sense language risks oversimplification. Such a definition may fail to capture the essence of sin as understood within different religious traditions, thereby hindering rather than facilitating dialogue.

On the contrary, I have written, "Sin is nothing else than a morally bad act" (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6). This suggests a possibility of describing sin in terms that are both accessible and compatible with my broader theological and philosophical teachings.

I answer that, sin, in its most fundamental sense, can be understood as a voluntary act, word, or desire contrary to the eternal law (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6). To frame this in common-sense language, one might say sin is knowingly choosing to do something that is fundamentally wrong or harmful, according to a standard of right and wrong that guides the universe. This definition aligns with the essence of my teaching while being expressed in terms that do not explicitly invoke religious or philosophical doctrines. It emphasizes the voluntariness of the act, its moral quality, and its opposition to a universal standard of good, which can serve as a starting point for dialogue across different epistemological views concerning religion.

Reply to Objection 1. While it is true that my conception of sin is deeply intertwined with theological and philosophical contexts, the essence of sin as a voluntary act contrary to the good can be articulated in a way that is understandable without requiring adherence to these frameworks. This approach maintains the integrity of the concept while making it accessible for interdisciplinary dialogue.

Reply to Objection 2. Although framing sin in common-sense language presents challenges, especially regarding the preservation of its depth across various traditions, a carefully crafted definition can serve as a bridge for dialogue. By focusing on the core aspects of sin that are universally recognizable—such as its voluntariness, moral dimension, and opposition to a perceived good—it is possible to create a foundation for discussion among individuals with diverse perspectives.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
The flaw in your proposed definition is the reliance on the notion of a standard that guides the universe. It is indeed framed in everyday language avoiding typically religious vocabulary, but the concept is still philosophical and presupposes a universe guided by moral standards.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 2. Whether a definition of sin can be provided that avoids any philosophical presuppositions, including the notion of a universal moral standard?

Objection 1. It seems that any attempt to define sin necessarily involves philosophical presuppositions. Even the most basic definitions of sin, including those that aim to be accessible and free from explicitly religious vocabulary, rely on underlying notions of morality, choice, and harm. These concepts themselves are philosophical and presuppose some form of judgment about right and wrong, good and bad.

Objection 2. Moreover, avoiding the notion of a universal moral standard while defining sin might lead to a relativistic perspective, where what is considered sinful can vary widely between cultures, individuals, and contexts. This variability could undermine the very purpose of establishing a common starting point for dialogue, as it fails to provide a stable or coherent concept of sin.

On the contrary, my definition of sin as a "word, deed, or desire against the eternal law" (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6) can be seen as inherently philosophical and religious. However, the challenge lies in translating this into common-sense language without these underpinnings, which seems to necessitate some level of abstraction or philosophical concept.

I answer that, a definition of sin that seeks to avoid any philosophical presuppositions, including the notion of a universal moral standard, must focus instead on observable behaviors and consequences that are widely recognized as harmful or wrong within human communities. Sin, in this context, could be described as actions or behaviors that cause unjust harm to others or oneself. This approach emphasizes the social and personal impact of actions, sidestepping the need for a metaphysical framework while still capturing the essence of moral wrongdoing. It reflects a common-sense understanding of actions that are generally frowned upon because they disrupt social harmony or personal well-being.

Reply to Objection 1. While it is true that completely avoiding philosophical presuppositions in defining sin is challenging, focusing on the consequences of actions rather than their alignment with a moral standard allows for a more pragmatic approach. This does not deny the philosophical complexities but seeks a minimalistic way to engage with the concept in a manner accessible to a broad audience.

Reply to Objection 2. Adopting a definition based on the harmful consequences of actions acknowledges the diversity of cultural, individual, and contextual understandings of what constitutes harm. This approach allows for a flexible yet recognizable concept of sin that can adapt to various dialogues and discussions, promoting a more inclusive conversation without relying on a fixed moral standard.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
The focus on observable harm that is unjust is an improvement. But it limits the concept to performed actions that have direct consequences while sin in its general form may be purely internal with the harm being invisible for a long time.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 3. Whether sin can be defined in terms of internal states or intentions without observable external harm, while avoiding philosophical presuppositions?

Objection 1. It seems that defining sin in terms of internal states or intentions necessarily involves philosophical or religious presuppositions, since it requires notions of intentionality, moral awareness, and the distinction between right and wrong. These are abstract concepts that cannot be fully divorced from their philosophical underpinnings.

Objection 2. Furthermore, focusing on internal states or intentions as sinful, independent of external actions or observable harm, may lead to subjective interpretations of what constitutes sin. This subjectivity could challenge the objective basis needed for a common starting point in dialogue, as it introduces a level of personal judgment and moral evaluation that varies greatly between individuals.

On the contrary, I have posited that sin involves not just external actions but also the will and intellect, stating that sin is "in the will in so far as the will adheres to something contrary to the rule of reason and the Divine law" (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.74, A.1). This suggests a broader understanding of sin that includes internal dimensions, such as intentions and desires.

I answer that, sin can be conceived as including not only actions that result in direct, observable harm but also those internal decisions and intentions that are knowingly contrary to what is recognized as good or right, even if this recognition is not explicitly tied to a universal moral standard. In common-sense language, sin could be described as making a choice or harboring an intention that one knows is wrong or harmful, even if this harm is not immediately visible or external. This approach captures the essence of sin as involving a personal dimension of moral awareness and decision-making, emphasizing the role of individual conscience in determining right from wrong based on a broadly understood concept of harm that includes emotional, psychological, and relational dimensions.

Reply to Objection 1. While it is challenging to completely avoid philosophical terms when discussing internal states or intentions, the focus on personal knowledge of right and wrong and the choice to act contrary to this knowledge offers a practical way to discuss sin in accessible terms. This approach relies on a common-sense understanding of personal integrity and the awareness of harm.

Reply to Objection 2. Although defining sin in terms of internal states or intentions introduces a subjective element, it also acknowledges the complexity of human morality and ethics, which are inherently subjective to some degree. By emphasizing the role of personal conscience and the recognition of harm, this definition allows for a nuanced conversation about sin that can accommodate diverse perspectives without necessitating agreement on a specific moral framework.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.74, A.1
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2074.htm#article1

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
How about the Polish phrase 'zgoda na syf'?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 4. Whether the phrase 'zgoda na syf' can encapsulate the concept of sin in common-sense language without philosophical presuppositions?

Objection 1. It might seem that the phrase 'zgoda na syf', translating loosely to 'consent to filth' or 'acceptance of mess/dirt', reduces the concept of sin to a colloquial and potentially trivializing expression. This could undermine the seriousness with which sin is traditionally regarded in philosophical and theological discussions.

Objection 2. Moreover, the phrase 'zgoda na syf' may not fully capture the internal aspects of sin, such as intentionality and moral awareness, since it focuses on an external metaphor of 'filth' or 'mess'. This could limit its ability to encompass the breadth of what constitutes sin, especially in terms of thoughts and desires that may not have direct external manifestations.

On the contrary, using everyday language to describe complex concepts can make them more accessible and relatable. The phrase 'zgoda na syf' metaphorically signifies a knowing tolerance or acceptance of that which is morally impure or corrupt, reflecting an internal state of consent to wrongdoing. This captures the essence of sin as a personal choice or disposition towards what is understood to be wrong, even within a non-philosophical framework.

I answer that, the phrase 'zgoda na syf' could serve as a starting point for a common-sense understanding of sin, emphasizing the aspect of personal choice and the moral recognition of wrong. Sin, in this light, can be seen as the acceptance or tolerance of actions, thoughts, or conditions that one knows to be detrimental to oneself or others, morally or otherwise. This conceptualization aligns with the notion that sin involves a willful engagement or complicity with wrongdoing, without necessarily invoking philosophical or theological doctrines. It reflects a practical understanding of sin as involving decisions and attitudes that contribute to moral or literal 'mess' in one's life or in the lives of others.

Reply to Objection 1. While the expression 'zgoda na syf' uses colloquial language, it does not necessarily trivialize the concept of sin. Instead, it offers a vivid and relatable way to discuss the willingness to engage with or tolerate moral wrongdoing, making the concept accessible to a broader audience.

Reply to Objection 2. Although the phrase employs an external metaphor, it implicitly includes the internal dimension of sin through the concept of 'consent' or 'acceptance'. This implies a deliberate internal choice, acknowledging the complexity of sin as encompassing both external actions and internal states.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
acceptatio sordium

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 5. Whether the Latin phrase 'acceptatio sordium' accurately captures the essence of sin in philosophical terms?

Objection 1. It might appear that the Latin phrase 'acceptatio sordium', directly translating to 'acceptance of dirtiness' or 'acceptance of filth', is too literal and physical in its imagery to fully encapsulate the metaphysical and moral dimensions of sin. Sin, as a concept, encompasses not only external actions but also internal dispositions, intentions, and the breach of moral and divine laws, which may not be adequately conveyed by the metaphor of physical filth.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the use of Latin, while lending a certain gravitas and historical depth to the discussion, might not facilitate understanding or engagement with the concept of sin across a broad spectrum of individuals, especially those unfamiliar with classical languages. This could potentially limit the phrase's effectiveness in serving as a bridge for dialogue about sin across different epistemological positions concerning religion.

On the contrary, Latin has been a traditional language of scholarship and theology, especially within the Christian tradition, and my own works extensively employ it to convey complex theological and philosophical ideas. The phrase 'acceptatio sordium' employs this venerable tradition to offer a concise, yet profound, conceptualization of sin that emphasizes the voluntary acceptance of moral impurity or corruption, which aligns with the understanding of sin as a deliberate turning away from the good.

I answer that, 'acceptatio sordium' can indeed serve as an effective philosophical term to describe the essence of sin, capturing its voluntary and moral dimensions. The phrase succinctly conveys the idea of willingly embracing or tolerating what is morally contaminating or corrupt, a notion that is central to the understanding of sin in my works. This acceptance indicates not merely a passive state but an active choice or consent to remain in a condition contrary to the moral order or divine law. Thus, while the metaphor of 'filth' is physical, it symbolically represents the moral and spiritual contamination that sin entails, making 'acceptatio sordium' a fitting description of sin within a philosophical or theological framework.

Reply to Objection 1. Although the phrase uses physical imagery, it is a metaphorical representation that effectively conveys the internal and external aspects of sin. The metaphor of 'filth' or 'dirtiness' is not uncommon in religious and philosophical discourse as a symbol for moral or spiritual impurity. Therefore, 'acceptatio sordium' can encapsulate the complexity of sin by highlighting the deliberate embrace of what is known to be morally wrong.

Reply to Objection 2. While the use of Latin may pose challenges for immediate accessibility, the phrase 'acceptatio sordium' offers depth and richness in understanding, connecting the discussion of sin to a long tradition of theological and philosophical inquiry. Moreover, the translation and explanation of such terms can facilitate engagement, bridging historical and conceptual insights with contemporary dialogues on morality and ethics.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
The best English equivalent for zgoda na syf and acceptatio sordium?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 6. Whether "consent to disorder" is the best English equivalent for 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'?

Objection 1. It may seem that "consent to disorder" does not fully capture the moral weight and nuance of 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'. The original phrases imply not just any disorder, but a specific kind of moral or spiritual filth. "Disorder" alone might suggest a lack of organization or chaos, rather than the moral wrongdoing or impurity implied by sin.

Objection 2. Moreover, "consent" suggests an active agreement or allowance, which accurately captures the voluntary aspect of sin. However, the term "disorder" might not sufficiently convey the concept of moral or ethical deviation that is central to the understanding of sin. This could lead to an interpretation of sin that emphasizes external chaos over internal moral failure.

On the contrary, the term "disorder" in a moral or spiritual context is understood to mean more than mere physical disarray; it implies a deviation from the natural or divine order, which is a fundamental aspect of sin in my works. Therefore, "consent to disorder" aptly reflects the voluntary alignment with or acceptance of a state contrary to this order.

I answer that, "consent to disorder" serves as an effective English equivalent for 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium' by conveying the essential elements of sin: the voluntary aspect (consent) and the moral or spiritual deviation (disorder). This translation bridges the conceptual gap between the colloquial and the classical, providing a phrase that encapsulates the willful embrace of or acquiescence to moral or spiritual corruption. While "consent to disorder" might initially seem to lack the specific connotation of filth or dirtiness, it effectively captures the broader, more abstract principle of sin as a departure from the proper order of things, whether that order is understood morally, ethically, or spiritually.

Reply to Objection 1. While "consent to disorder" may not directly convey the imagery of filth, it encompasses the underlying concept of sin as a voluntary state of moral or spiritual impurity. The emphasis on consent highlights the active choice involved in sin, and the term disorder aptly signifies the breach of moral or divine law.

Reply to Objection 2. The use of "disorder" to represent the concept of sin does indeed focus on the aspect of deviation from an established order, which is central to the understanding of sin. This choice of words maintains the balance between the internal (moral or spiritual failure) and the external (observable consequences of actions) dimensions of sin, reflecting its comprehensive nature as both an internal state of being and its manifestation in actions.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
But disorder is either a philosophical concept already or a concept that is not inherently morally wrong. A disorder is just lack of order. One may tolerate 'lack of order' in many circumstances, but one may not tolerate filth.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 7. Whether "tolerance of corruption" is a more suitable English equivalent for 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'?

Objection 1. It might seem that "tolerance of corruption" shifts the emphasis too much towards a political or economic interpretation of corruption, potentially overshadowing the moral and spiritual dimensions of sin. The term 'corruption' is often associated with bribery, dishonesty, and decay in societal institutions, which might not fully encompass the personal and internal aspects of sin as understood in a theological context.

Objection 2. Moreover, by focusing on "tolerance," the phrase may imply a passive acceptance rather than the active consent implied by 'zgoda' and 'acceptatio'. This could suggest a less volitional aspect to sin, where the emphasis is on enduring or putting up with corruption, rather than actively choosing or consenting to it.

On the contrary, the term 'corruption' in its broader sense signifies not only societal or institutional decay but also moral degradation and the perversion of integrity or purity. Thus, "tolerance of corruption" can effectively convey the essence of sin as the willful acceptance or allowance of moral and spiritual degradation, aligning with the conceptual depth of 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'.

I answer that, "tolerance of corruption" indeed captures the essence of the phrases 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium' by emphasizing both the moral wrongdoing and the voluntary aspect of sin. This translation acknowledges the complexity of sin as involving an active or passive alignment with a state of moral degradation, whether through thoughts, desires, or actions. By using "corruption," the phrase highlights the deterioration of moral integrity, which is central to the concept of sin. Furthermore, "tolerance" can encompass both the active consent to and the passive acceptance of such moral degradation, offering a nuanced understanding of the individual's role in sin.

Reply to Objection 1. While "corruption" may have specific connotations in political and economic contexts, its use here is intended to signify a broader sense of moral and spiritual decay. This interpretation aligns with the theological understanding of sin as a deviation from moral and divine law, capturing the depth of moral failure and degradation.

Reply to Objection 2. The term "tolerance" indeed suggests a range of engagement with corruption, from passive acceptance to active consent. This breadth allows for a more inclusive understanding of sin, reflecting the various ways in which individuals may relate to moral wrongdoing. It acknowledges that sin can manifest not only through deliberate actions but also through acquiescence to or failure to resist conditions of moral corruption.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
But why not simply use the word filth? Is it not appropriate? Corruption is indeed used in a political sense, and also it presupposes an earlier better state, while filth may be the initial state of affairs to be opposed.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 8. Whether "consent to filth" is the most appropriate English translation for 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'?

Objection 1. It might appear that "consent to filth" is overly simplistic and fails to capture the full moral and spiritual implications of sin. The term 'filth' primarily conveys physical uncleanliness or impurity, which may not adequately reflect the complexity of sin as involving a breach of moral and divine law.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the term 'filth' might lack the nuanced connotations necessary to fully encompass the internal dimension of sin, such as wrongful intentions, desires, or thoughts. This could lead to an interpretation of sin that overly emphasizes its external manifestations, neglecting the importance of the internal aspect.

On the contrary, the term 'filth' can metaphorically represent moral and spiritual impurity, making "consent to filth" a potent and direct translation of 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'. This phrase emphasizes the voluntary aspect of sin, highlighting the individual's active or passive agreement to engage with or tolerate moral degradation. In this sense, 'filth' serves as a powerful symbol of the corruption of one's moral or spiritual state, capturing both the internal and external dimensions of sin.

I answer that, "consent to filth" indeed captures the essence of sin as understood in both the phrases 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'. By employing the term 'filth', the translation directly conveys the concept of moral and spiritual impurity, emphasizing the condition that sin represents—a deviation from the good, the pure, and the holy. The use of 'consent' accurately reflects the volitional aspect of sin, indicating an individual's choice to align with or accept this state of impurity. This choice can manifest in thoughts, desires, actions, or a lack of action against what is recognized as morally degrading. Thus, "consent to filth" effectively communicates the multidimensional nature of sin, encompassing both its internal motivations and external expressions.

Reply to Objection 1. While 'filth' primarily denotes physical uncleanliness, its metaphorical use in describing sin captures the profound impact of moral and spiritual impurity. This usage aligns with the traditional religious imagery that equates sin with contamination or defilement, providing a vivid depiction of the moral state to be avoided.

Reply to Objection 2. The metaphorical richness of the term 'filth' allows for the inclusion of the internal dimension of sin, as it can symbolize not only the visible consequences of sin but also the invisible moral and spiritual degradation. The emphasis on 'consent' further ensures that the definition encompasses the internal decision-making process that leads to sin, whether those decisions result in external actions or remain in the realm of thought and desire.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Once filth is considered the best word, how to choose between acceptance, consent and assent in our phrase?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 9. Whether "acceptance," "consent," or "assent" best complements "filth" in accurately translating 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'?

Objection 1. It might seem that "acceptance of filth" best captures the essence of the original phrases, as it implies a passive willingness to allow filth to remain, without necessarily endorsing or agreeing with it actively. This could suggest a broader range of engagement with moral impurity, from mere tolerance to explicit approval.

Objection 2. On the other hand, "assent to filth" implies a more intellectual agreement or acknowledgment of filth, potentially missing the volitional aspect of sin that involves a choice or action beyond mere intellectual acknowledgment. This might render the translation too passive or cognitive, neglecting the active engagement with sin.

Objection 3. "Consent to filth" suggests an active agreement or permission that involves both recognition and volition, which might be too strong in some contexts where sin is more about negligence or failing to resist rather than actively choosing or endorsing moral impurity.

On the contrary, the term "consent" captures both the active and passive dimensions of engaging with sin, as it involves an element of choice or permission, whether through action or inaction. This makes "consent to filth" a balanced and accurate translation that reflects the multifaceted nature of sin, encompassing both deliberate actions and negligent tolerances.

I answer that, among "acceptance," "consent," and "assent," "consent to filth" most effectively encapsulates the concept of sin as represented by 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium'. Consent implies an active engagement with the choice at hand, which can include both explicit agreement to engage in wrongful acts and implicit agreement through failure to oppose or remove oneself from situations of moral impurity. This term, therefore, captures the nuanced reality of sin, which can manifest through direct actions as well as through passive complicity or failure to act against wrong.

Reply to Objection 1. While "acceptance of filth" does convey a broad engagement with sin, it lacks the emphasis on the volitional aspect that is crucial to the concept of sin as a deliberate deviation from moral goodness. Sin involves more than passive tolerance; it involves an element of willful engagement, whether through action or deliberate inaction.

Reply to Objection 2. "Assent to filth," though capturing the cognitive aspect of agreeing with sin, fails to fully encompass the active and passive ways in which individuals engage with sin. Sin is not merely an intellectual acknowledgment but involves the will and actions.

Reply to Objection 3. Although "consent to filth" may seem to imply a strong active agreement, it also allows for the interpretation of sin as occurring through negligence or failure to act. Consent can be understood in a broad sense that includes various forms of engagement with moral impurity, making it the most suitable choice for capturing the essence of sin in this context.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Perhaps consent (via the prefix con) presupposes the existence of multiple parties patraking in the consent. This should be avoided if we want to allow the concept of sin to be strictly individual.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 10. Whether "acquiescence to filth" is the most fitting translation for 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium', considering the strictly individual aspect of sin?

Objection 1. It might seem that "acquiescence to filth" could imply too passive a stance towards sin, focusing more on silent agreement or passive acceptance without the active decision-making process often involved in sinning. This could detract from the understanding of sin as involving deliberate choices and actions.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the term 'acquiescence' may not fully capture the sense of personal responsibility and agency in sin, as it leans towards the idea of reluctantly giving in rather than actively choosing or engaging in moral wrongdoing. This might underrepresent the aspect of willful engagement with sin.

On the contrary, 'acquiescence' precisely captures the essence of sin when considered as a strictly individual act, by emphasizing the personal submission or passive consent to wrongdoing without necessarily implying the involvement of others. It encompasses both the active and passive dimensions of sin—actively choosing not to oppose filth and passively allowing oneself to remain in a state of moral impurity.

I answer that, "acquiescence to filth" effectively translates 'zgoda na syf' and 'acceptatio sordium', particularly when highlighting sin as an individual act. This phrase aptly describes the process of individually acknowledging, yet not resisting, the pull of moral impurity. Acquiescence captures the nuanced reality of sin that includes not only the explicit actions taken towards wrongdoing but also the implicit acceptance of such a state through inaction or passive endurance. It reflects the individual's role in sin without presupposing the active consent between multiple parties, thereby focusing on the internal struggle and personal decision to not oppose sin.

Reply to Objection 1. Although "acquiescence to filth" may suggest a degree of passivity, it does not exclude the active element inherent in the decision to acquiesce. The term can encompass a range of engagements with sin, from a more passive tolerance to an active decision not to resist or remove oneself from situations of moral impurity.

Reply to Objection 2. The concept of acquiescence inherently includes personal responsibility and agency, as it involves the choice—whether active or passive—to not combat or remove oneself from the presence of filth. This choice signifies a form of personal complicity in sin, capturing the individual's moral responsibility.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
My quick internet search found "the reluctant acceptance of something without protest." as the definition of acquiessence. If the 'reluctant' element is inherent in this word, then perhaps it should be avoided. Or perhaps on the contrary, this reluctance may be viewed as the reality considering that we are drawn to goodness by default. What do you think?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 11. Whether the inherent "reluctance" in "acquiescence to filth" suitably captures the nature of sin?

Objection 1. It may seem inappropriate to include the element of reluctance in the concept of sin, as this could suggest that sinning is always against one's better judgment or inherent disposition towards goodness. This perspective might overlook the complexity of human freedom and the capacity for individuals to willingly choose wrong without reluctance.

Objection 2. Additionally, framing sin with an inherent reluctance could imply that all acts of sin are committed with a consciousness of their moral wrongness and an internal resistance, which might not accurately represent the diverse states of mind and motivations behind sinful actions. Some may sin with deliberate intent and without any apparent reluctance, driven by various motivations or misunderstandings of the good.

On the contrary, the element of reluctance in "acquiescence to filth" can be seen as reflecting a profound theological truth about human nature: that humans, created in the image of God and oriented towards the good, find in themselves a natural resistance to evil. This reluctance can be understood as a testament to the innate draw towards goodness, even in the midst of sinning, highlighting the conflict within the human soul between its higher aspirations and its fallen actions.

I answer that, the inclusion of "reluctance" in the understanding of "acquiescence to filth" offers a nuanced insight into the condition of sin. This reluctance acknowledges the fundamental orientation of the human will towards the good, as articulated in the natural law theory, which posits that humans are naturally inclined to seek what is good and avoid what is evil. The reality of sinning, then, involves a complex interplay between this natural inclination towards the good and the choices that lead one away from it. The reluctance embedded in acquiescence suggests that, at some level, even in the act of sinning, there is an awareness—however obscured—of a deviation from this natural inclination towards goodness. This does not diminish the responsibility or freedom involved in sinning but rather highlights the tragic aspect of sin as a failure to fully embrace the good that one is naturally drawn towards.

Reply to Objection 1. While it is true that sin can be chosen willingly and without apparent reluctance, the concept of reluctance in "acquiescence to filth" does not negate the possibility of such choices. Instead, it emphasizes the underlying tension within the human condition between the pull of sin and the orientation towards goodness, a tension that exists even when not consciously acknowledged.

Reply to Objection 2. Acknowledging reluctance does not imply that all sinful actions are committed under duress or against one's will. Rather, it reflects the complexity of human freedom, where the choice to sin is often made in the context of conflicting desires and motivations, including the obscured but persistent draw towards what is genuinely good.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
If this phrase is so good then perhaps the original zgoda na syf should be improved to przyzwolenie na syf.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 12. Whether 'przyzwolenie na syf' is a more accurate and nuanced Polish phrase than 'zgoda na syf' to reflect the concept of 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It might appear that changing 'zgoda' to 'przyzwolenie' is unnecessary, as both terms can be understood to imply a form of agreement or acceptance. 'Zgoda na syf' already effectively communicates the idea of consent to moral impurity or degradation, making the modification to 'przyzwolenie na syf' seem redundant.

Objection 2. Furthermore, 'przyzwolenie' might introduce a level of formality or specificity that is not inherently present in 'zgoda', potentially narrowing the scope of the phrase's applicability. The original 'zgoda na syf' offers a broader interpretation that could encompass various degrees of consent, including the nuanced concept of acquiescence.

On the contrary, 'przyzwolenie' carries connotations of permission or allowance that might better capture the nuanced concept of acquiescence, which involves a more passive form of agreement or tolerance. This term emphasizes the aspect of allowing or permitting something to occur, which aligns closely with the idea of acquiescence to filth, suggesting a subtle but important distinction from active consent.

I answer that, 'przyzwolenie na syf' enhances the original phrase 'zgoda na syf' by more precisely capturing the essence of 'acquiescence to filth'. While 'zgoda' implies agreement or consent, 'przyzwolenie' emphasizes a form of permission that may be more passive and reluctant, reflecting the complexity of the human moral experience. This shift from 'zgoda' to 'przyzwolenie' acknowledges the internal conflict and the often passive nature of sin as an acceptance of moral degradation, even when such acceptance conflicts with one's better judgment or natural inclination towards the good. Therefore, 'przyzwolenie na syf' more accurately conveys the nuanced dynamics of moral failure, highlighting the tragic reality of sin as both an individual and collective failure to uphold the good.

Reply to Objection 1. While 'zgoda' and 'przyzwolenie' are conceptually related, the latter offers a deeper insight into the passive and sometimes reluctant nature of sin, thus providing a richer understanding of moral degradation. The distinction, though subtle, is significant in capturing the essence of acquiescence.

Reply to Objection 2. The specificity introduced by 'przyzwolenie' does not limit the phrase's applicability but rather enriches it by highlighting the passive dimension of consent to sin. This specificity helps to articulate the nuanced reality of moral and spiritual degradation, making 'przyzwolenie na syf' a more precise and illuminating phrase.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Can you improve the Latin phrase too?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 13. Whether 'concessio sordium' is an improved Latin phrase over 'acceptatio sordium' to mirror the nuanced concept of 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It might seem unnecessary to replace 'acceptatio' with 'concessio', as 'acceptatio sordium' already effectively conveys the concept of accepting or receiving filth, capturing the essence of moral degradation. The modification to 'concessio sordium' might be seen as an unnecessary refinement that does not significantly alter the phrase's meaning.

Objection 2. Moreover, 'concessio' implies a granting or yielding, which could suggest an even more passive stance than 'acceptatio', potentially obscuring the active engagement or consent inherent in the concept of sin. This might lead to an interpretation of sin that overly emphasizes passivity, neglecting the aspect of willful engagement.

On the contrary, 'concessio' precisely captures the nuanced concept of acquiescence, which involves not merely passive acceptance but a more nuanced yielding or permitting, especially in contexts where resistance is possible but not enacted. This term emphasizes the reluctant permission given to moral degradation, aligning closely with the idea of acquiescence to filth and reflecting a deeper understanding of the moral dynamics at play.

I answer that, 'concessio sordium' offers a more accurate Latin rendering of the concept encapsulated in 'przyzwolenie na syf' and 'acquiescence to filth'. While 'acceptatio sordium' suggests a reception or acceptance of filth, 'concessio sordium' introduces the dimension of reluctant permission or yielding to filth, capturing the complex interplay of agency and passivity in the face of moral degradation. This term more effectively communicates the subtleties of moral failure, emphasizing the tragic aspect of sin as a yielding to lesser goods in the absence of the good for which we are naturally inclined. Thus, 'concessio sordium' enriches the original phrase by highlighting the nuanced reality of sin as both an individual and communal moral failing.

Reply to Objection 1. Although 'acceptatio' and 'concessio' are conceptually similar, the shift to 'concessio' provides a clearer depiction of the nuanced moral reality sin represents. This refinement is not merely semantic but offers a deeper insight into the nature of moral acquiescence, making it a significant improvement.

Reply to Objection 2. The emphasis on 'concessio' as a yielding or granting does not negate the active aspect of sin but rather complements it by acknowledging the complexity of human moral decisions. Sin involves both the actions taken and the failures to act against moral degradation, and 'concessio sordium' aptly reflects this dual nature.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
I think that the majority of sins, especially those most hotly contested, are not active performances but rather hidden agreements involving pangs or indecision or lack of clarity.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 14. Whether the majority of sins, particularly those most contentiously debated, primarily consist of hidden agreements, pangs of conscience, indecision, or lack of clarity rather than active deeds?

Objection 1. It might appear that focusing on sins as primarily hidden agreements or the result of indecision diminishes the significance of active, deliberate sins. This perspective could lead to underestimating the moral responsibility individuals have for overt actions that are clearly wrong.

Objection 2. Furthermore, emphasizing the hidden or internal aspects of sin might complicate the process of moral evaluation and repentance. If sin is predominantly seen as an internal struggle or ambiguity, it could become more challenging for individuals to recognize, confess, and amend their ways, potentially blurring the lines between sin and mere moral uncertainty.

On the contrary, I have argued that sin is located in the will, stating that "sin is nothing else than a bad human act" (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6), and that an act becomes sinful through deviation from reason and Divine law, not necessarily through external action alone. This suggests a broad understanding of sin that includes internal dispositions and decisions, even in the absence of external acts.

I answer that, the majority of sins, especially those that provoke significant debate, often do reside in the realm of hidden agreements, internal conflicts, and moral ambiguities rather than in overt actions. This understanding of sin acknowledges the complexity of human moral life, where many wrongdoings stem from subtler forms of consent to evil—such as willful ignorance, deliberate indecision, or suppressed conscience—rather than from direct actions. This perspective does not diminish the moral weight of active sins but rather expands the concept of sin to include the myriad ways individuals can fail to align their will with the good. Recognizing the internal dimensions of sin highlights the importance of ongoing self-reflection, discernment, and the cultivation of virtue to navigate these moral complexities.

Reply to Objection 1. Acknowledging that many sins are rooted in hidden agreements or internal struggles does not detract from the gravity of active sins but complements this understanding by recognizing the full spectrum of moral failure. This approach calls for a deeper engagement with one's conscience and moral reasoning, emphasizing the need for vigilance in all aspects of moral life.

Reply to Objection 2. While focusing on the internal aspects of sin might present challenges in terms of moral clarity and repentance, it also fosters a more profound understanding of sin's nature. By recognizing the importance of internal dispositions and the subtleties of moral decision-making, individuals are encouraged to cultivate a more discerning and sensitive conscience, which is essential for authentic moral growth and transformation.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
The purpose of our phrases is to inform dialogue where difference of opinion is present. We do not need to clarify the concept of sin in the most obvious cases where general agreement obtains.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 15. Whether the phrases 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' are primarily intended to facilitate dialogue in contexts of moral disagreement, rather than to address universally recognized sins?

Objection 1. It may seem that by focusing on nuanced phrases like 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth', we risk obscuring the clarity needed in discussions of sin, especially in cases where there is widespread agreement on moral wrongs. This focus on the subtleties of moral failure might dilute the force of moral discourse in areas of clear ethical consensus.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the emphasis on facilitating dialogue in areas of moral disagreement through these phrases might inadvertently suggest that sin is a matter of subjective interpretation rather than objective moral truth. This could weaken the foundational belief in universal moral standards, leading to relativism.

On the contrary, the purpose of formulating such nuanced phrases is to deepen understanding and foster constructive dialogue in areas of moral ambiguity and contention. Recognizing the complexity of human moral experience, especially in contested areas, does not negate the existence of objective moral truths but rather acknowledges the challenges inherent in discerning and applying these truths in specific contexts.

I answer that, the phrases 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' serve an important purpose in moral dialogue, particularly in contexts where differences of opinion and interpretation are prevalent. By emphasizing the subtler forms of moral failure—those that are often the subject of debate and disagreement—these phrases invite a more nuanced and compassionate engagement with the complexities of sin. They acknowledge that many moral failings are not the result of clear, deliberate choices but rather arise from internal conflicts, ambiguities, and the failure to act against wrongdoing. In doing so, these phrases do not obscure the reality of sin but illuminate its less visible dimensions, encouraging a dialogue that is both more inclusive and more reflective of the full spectrum of moral experience.

Reply to Objection 1. The use of nuanced phrases to address complex moral issues does not diminish the clarity or force of moral discourse but enriches it. By providing language that captures the more elusive aspects of sin, these phrases enhance our ability to engage with and address moral failures that might otherwise be overlooked or misunderstood.

Reply to Objection 2. Facilitating dialogue on contentious moral issues through these carefully chosen phrases does not lead to relativism but promotes a deeper exploration of objective moral truths. By acknowledging the diversity of human experiences and the challenges of moral discernment, these phrases encourage a more thorough and empathetic search for the good, grounded in a recognition of our shared fallibility and our common call to virtue.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Why do you think these phrases are not in common use?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 16. Whether the rarity of phrases like 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' in common discourse indicates a deficiency in moral language?

Objection 1. It might seem that these phrases are not in common use because they are overly specific or nuanced for everyday conversations about morality. The general public may prefer simpler, more direct language when discussing right and wrong, making these precise formulations less appealing for widespread adoption.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the lack of common use of these phrases could be attributed to a cultural preference for discussing sin and morality in terms of external actions rather than internal dispositions or subtle forms of consent. This focus on overt behaviors over internal states may diminish the perceived relevance of such nuanced expressions in moral dialogue.

On the contrary, the rarity of these phrases in common discourse might reflect a gap in the collective moral vocabulary, indicating a need for more precise language to capture the complexities of moral experience. The absence of such terms from widespread use suggests an opportunity to enrich moral conversations by introducing expressions that more accurately reflect the nuanced realities of sin and moral decision-making.

I answer that, the infrequency of phrases like 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' in common use does not necessarily indicate their irrelevance but rather points to a deficiency in the common moral lexicon. These phrases encapsulate aspects of moral experience that are often overlooked or inadequately expressed in everyday language. Their rarity in common discourse may be due to a combination of factors, including the complexity of the concepts they represent, societal discomfort with confronting subtle forms of moral failure, and a lack of awareness about the depth and breadth of moral agency. By incorporating such phrases into moral dialogue, there is potential to foster a more nuanced understanding of sin, emphasizing the importance of internal dispositions, the subtleties of consent, and the moral significance of passive acceptance of wrongdoing. This enriched vocabulary could lead to deeper reflection, more honest self-assessment, and more constructive discussions about morality and ethics.

Reply to Objection 1. While simpler language may be more accessible for everyday use, the complexity of moral reality necessitates a richer vocabulary to capture its subtleties. The development and adoption of more nuanced phrases can complement simpler moral language, providing the tools needed for more detailed and accurate discussions of ethics.

Reply to Objection 2. The cultural tendency to focus on external actions in discussions of morality does not negate the importance of internal states and subtler forms of moral engagement. By introducing and popularizing phrases that highlight these aspects, it is possible to shift cultural perceptions and encourage a more comprehensive approach to understanding and discussing sin and virtue.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Even John Paul II never used these phrases, instead constantly relying on locutions borrowed from your own works.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 17. Whether the reliance on traditional locutions from my works by John Paul II, rather than employing phrases like 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth', signifies a preference for established theological language in addressing moral issues?

Objection 1. It might seem that John Paul II's preference for traditional theological language, specifically terms and phrases drawn from my works, over more contemporary or nuanced expressions like 'przyzwolenie na syf' or 'concessio sordium', indicates a limitation in the church's willingness to adapt its moral vocabulary to changing times and understandings. This could suggest a reluctance to fully engage with the complexities of modern moral experiences.

Objection 2. Furthermore, this reliance on established locutions could be interpreted as a lack of innovation in moral theology, potentially hindering the Church's ability to communicate effectively with contemporary audiences who might relate more readily to newer expressions of moral concepts.

On the contrary, John Paul II's use of traditional theological language and specifically terms from my works signifies a deep commitment to a consistent and unified moral and theological vision. This approach ensures that the Church's teachings remain rooted in a solid and historically grounded framework, even while addressing the challenges of the modern world. The use of established language does not preclude the exploration of new expressions but serves as a foundation upon which further dialogue and understanding can be built.

I answer that, John Paul II's preference for utilizing traditional theological locutions, including those from my works, rather than adopting newer phrases such as 'przyzwolenie na syf' or 'concessio sordium', reflects a strategic and thoughtful approach to moral and theological discourse. This choice underscores the importance of continuity, clarity, and depth in conveying the Church's teachings. By grounding his discussions in well-established theological terms, John Paul II ensured that his messages were anchored in the rich intellectual tradition of the Church, facilitating a dialogue that bridges past and present understandings of morality. Moreover, this approach allowed for a deep engagement with complex moral issues in a manner that is both accessible and profound, leveraging the cumulative wisdom of the Church's intellectual heritage to address contemporary challenges. The use of traditional language does not negate the relevance of new expressions but rather enriches the conversation, providing a stable framework within which new insights and expressions can be explored and understood in relation to the enduring truths of the faith.

Reply to Objection 1. The Church's commitment to traditional theological language, exemplified by John Paul II, does not signify a reluctance to engage with modern complexities but rather a dedication to ensuring that such engagement is deeply rooted in a coherent and comprehensive moral and theological vision.

Reply to Objection 2. The reliance on established locutions represents not a lack of innovation but a profound understanding of the value of continuity and depth in moral theology. This approach allows for the effective communication of the Church's teachings, ensuring that they are both relatable and grounded in a solid theological tradition.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Starting from these phrases write a whole Question subdivided into Articles that develops the argument that (1) they capture the essence of your concept of sin, and (2) they can be reliably used for dialogue between any differening positions.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Question 18: On the suitability of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' for capturing the essence of sin and facilitating dialogue across differing positions.


Article 1. Whether 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' capture the essence of the concept of sin as articulated by Aquinas?

Objection 1. It seems that these phrases might oversimplify the concept of sin, focusing too much on the aspect of passive consent and neglecting the active and deliberate dimensions of sinning, which are central to Aquinas's understanding.

Objection 2. Moreover, by emphasizing the metaphor of 'filth', these phrases might limit the concept of sin to moral impurity, overlooking other dimensions of sin such as the disruption of order, the privation of good, and the offense against God.

On the contrary, I have posited that sin fundamentally involves a turn away from the eternal law and a disorder of the will (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6), suggesting that consent, whether active or passive, to that which contradicts the good, indeed captures the essence of sin.

I answer that, 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' effectively encapsulate the essence of sin by emphasizing the willful engagement or passive tolerance of moral degradation. These phrases highlight the internal dimension of sin—consent of the will to that which is contrary to the good. This internal consent is crucial for understanding the nature of sin, aligning with my assertion that sin is primarily an act of the will against God's eternal law. The metaphor of 'filth' symbolically represents not just moral impurity but the broader disorder and deviation from the good that sin entails, thus encompassing the multifaceted nature of sin.

Reply to Objection 1. While active and deliberate actions are significant, the emphasis on acquiescence underscores the importance of the will's orientation, which is fundamental to the nature of sin. This does not negate the active dimensions but complements them by highlighting the role of consent in sin.

Reply to Objection 2. The metaphor of 'filth' serves as a vivid symbol for the broader concept of sin, including disruption of order and privation of good. It is not limited to moral impurity but extends to all forms of deviation from the divine good.


Article 2. Whether 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' can be reliably used for dialogue between differing positions on morality?

Objection 1. It may appear that these phrases, with their emphasis on 'filth', might be too laden with negative connotations to facilitate open and productive dialogue, especially among those who might not share the same moral framework.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the specificity and nuance of these phrases might make them less accessible to those unfamiliar with theological or philosophical discourse, potentially limiting their usefulness in broader dialogues.

On the contrary, the depth and nuance of these phrases offer a rich vocabulary for discussing the complexities of moral decision-making and sin, providing a common ground for dialogue that transcends specific religious or moral frameworks.

I answer that, 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' serve as valuable tools for dialogue across differing positions by offering a nuanced and comprehensive understanding of sin that emphasizes internal dispositions and the moral significance of consent. These phrases encourage a deeper exploration of the conditions and motivations underlying moral actions and failures, inviting participants in dialogue to consider the internal as well as external dimensions of sin. By focusing on the concept of acquiescence, the discussion is opened to explore the varied ways in which individuals and communities navigate moral complexities, making these phrases particularly suited to fostering understanding and empathy across diverse perspectives.

Reply to Objection 1. The use of vivid metaphors like 'filth' can actually enhance dialogue by providing a concrete symbol for abstract moral concepts, facilitating deeper emotional and intellectual engagement with the topic.

Reply to Objection 2. While these phrases are nuanced, their grounding in common human experiences of moral struggle and failure makes them accessible entry points for discussions on the nature of sin, inviting broader participation in moral dialogue.


References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
There is an intriguing corollary from these phrases. In a world without filth there is no sin!

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 18. Whether the absence of 'filth' entails the absence of sin in the world?

Objection 1. It might seem that if 'filth'—understood metaphorically as moral impurity or degradation—is absent, then sin, too, would be absent. This conclusion appears logical, as sin and moral 'filth' are closely related concepts, with sin often manifesting as actions, thoughts, or dispositions that deviate from moral goodness.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the conceptualization of a world without 'filth' suggests a state of perfect moral order and goodness, where all actions and intentions align with the divine will. In such a world, the conditions that give rise to sin would not exist, thereby eliminating sin itself.

On the contrary, the absence of 'filth' in the world does not necessarily mean the absence of sin. Sin originates not only from the external presence of moral 'filth' but from the will's orientation towards or away from the ultimate good, which is God (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6). Sin is fundamentally a deviation from the eternal law, rooted in the misuse of free will, rather than merely a reaction to external conditions of 'filth'.

I answer that, a world without 'filth'—understood as moral impurity—does not automatically preclude the existence of sin. Sin is primarily an act of the will, a turning away from God and His law, which can occur even in a context that appears externally 'clean' or devoid of temptation. The absence of 'filth' could, theoretically, reduce occasions for sin, but it does not address the root of sin: the free will's capacity to choose contrary to the good. Sin's essence lies in the willful rejection of the good, regardless of the external circumstances. Therefore, the elimination of external 'filth' would not, by itself, eradicate sin, as the potential for moral failure resides within the human heart's capacity to choose.

Reply to Objection 1. While sin often manifests through engagement with moral 'filth', its root is in the willful orientation of the human heart away from the good. Therefore, the mere absence of 'filth' does not guarantee the absence of sin.

Reply to Objection 2. A world without 'filth' might imply a reduction in opportunities for sin but does not eliminate the fundamental capacity for sin that exists within the exercise of free will. True freedom includes the possibility of choosing against the good, which is the essence of sin.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
In a world without (external) filth, filth must first enter the mind as an option, before the act of the will can acquiesse to it.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 19. Whether, in a world devoid of external 'filth', sin originates as an internal concept before the will can acquiesce to it?

Objection 1. It might seem that in the absence of external 'filth', the concept of 'filth' or sin cannot arise, as moral concepts are often developed in response to external stimuli and conditions. Without external 'filth', there would be no occasion for sin to enter the mind as an option.

Objection 2. Furthermore, if 'filth' must first enter the mind as an option in a world without external 'filth', this suggests that sin is fundamentally a product of the intellect rather than the will, contradicting the idea that sin is primarily an act of the will as I have posited (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6).

On the contrary, I have maintained that sin is a deviation from the eternal law, rooted in the misuse of free will (Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6). This suggests that the potential for sin, including the conceptualization of 'filth', originates from within the individual's capacity for moral judgment and choice, independent of external conditions.

I answer that, in a world devoid of external 'filth', the emergence of 'filth' as a concept or option within the mind underscores the innate capacity of human intellect and will to conceive of and engage with moral realities beyond immediate external stimuli. The intellect can discern between good and evil, and the will can choose between them, even in the absence of external provocations. This internal capacity for moral discernment and choice means that 'filth'—understood as the option to deviate from the good—can originate within the mind before the will acquiesces to it. This process highlights the profound role of human freedom and moral agency, which allows for the possibility of sin even in an ostensibly 'clean' external environment. The inclination towards or conceptualization of sin, therefore, is not solely contingent upon external 'filth' but can arise from the depths of human freedom and the complex interplay between intellect and will.

Reply to Objection 1. The absence of external 'filth' does not preclude the mind's ability to conceive of moral deviations. Human creativity and intellect can imagine scenarios and moral choices beyond those directly experienced, making 'filth' a conceivable option even in a pristine environment.

Reply to Objection 2. While the intellect presents options between good and evil, sin remains fundamentally an act of the will—a deliberate choice to deviate from the good. The entry of 'filth' into the mind as a concept does not make sin a product of the intellect but rather highlights the intellect's role in presenting choices upon which the will acts.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Are our phrases useful to decode the myth of the Garden of Eden and the temptation and fall?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Question 20: On the applicability of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' in interpreting the myth of the Garden of Eden, the temptation, and the fall.


Article 20. Whether the phrases 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' offer a useful lens for decoding the myth of the Garden of Eden, including the temptation and fall?

Objection 1. It might seem that these phrases, with their emphasis on moral degradation and consent to 'filth', are too specific to illuminate the broader theological and existential dimensions of the Eden narrative. The story encompasses themes of obedience, trust, and the loss of innocence, which might not be fully captured by the concept of acquiescing to 'filth'.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the narrative of the Garden of Eden involves a direct act of disobedience—eating the forbidden fruit—rather than a passive acquiescence to moral 'filth'. This suggests that the phrases might not accurately reflect the active nature of the sin committed by Adam and Eve.

On the contrary, the temptation and fall in the Garden of Eden can be understood as a paradigmatic instance of 'acquiescence to filth', insofar as it involves the willful choice to deviate from God's commandment based on a deceitful promise of greater knowledge and autonomy. This narrative highlights the fundamental dynamics of sin as a turning away from divine order and goodness, which is precisely what 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' seek to encapsulate.

I answer that, 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' provide a profound framework for interpreting the myth of the Garden of Eden, the temptation, and the fall. These phrases underscore the essential role of human freedom and consent in the presence of temptation and the commission of sin. The Eden narrative, at its core, is about the human choice to embrace or reject the divine will. The act of eating the forbidden fruit, prompted by the serpent's temptation, represents a deliberate acquiescence to a 'filth'—understood as disobedience and moral deviation—that was previously absent from the pristine purity of Eden. This moment of consent, where Adam and Eve choose to align themselves with the serpent's deception rather than with God's command, encapsulates the tragic reality of sin entering the world. Thus, the phrases in question illuminate the Eden story by highlighting the pivotal role of human choice and the moral and existential consequences of acquiescing to 'filth'.

Reply to Objection 1. While the Eden narrative encompasses a broad range of theological themes, the concept of acquiescing to 'filth' directly addresses the critical moment of moral failure—choosing against God's command—which is central to the story's meaning. This focus does not diminish the narrative's complexity but rather provides a lens through which its core moral lesson can be deeply understood.

Reply to Objection 2. Although the act of disobedience in Eden was indeed active, it was predicated on a prior internal acquiescence to the temptation presented by the serpent. This internal consent to deviate from God's commandment is what 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' seek to capture, reflecting the deeper dynamics of sin beyond the physical act itself.

References:

  1. Summa Theologica, I-II, Q.71, A.6
    https://www.newadvent.org/summa/2071.htm#article6

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Is the concept of filth really present in this myth? Perhaps our phrases are inept from the start.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 21. Whether the concept of 'filth', as implied by 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth', is apt for interpreting the myth of the Garden of Eden?

Objection 1. It might seem that the concept of 'filth' is not directly present in the Eden narrative, as the story does not describe moral degradation in terms of impurity or filthiness. The primary themes of disobedience, trust, and the loss of innocence might not align with the metaphorical use of 'filth', suggesting that our phrases might be inept for this context.

Objection 2. Moreover, the Eden narrative is fundamentally about the introduction of sin into the world through a specific act of disobedience, rather than an acquiescence to an existing state of moral 'filth'. This suggests that the concept of 'filth' may not accurately capture the essence of the original sin as depicted in the myth.

On the contrary, while the term 'filth' may not be explicitly mentioned in the Eden narrative, the concept can metaphorically represent the spiritual and moral corruption introduced by sin. The act of disobedience, prompted by the serpent's temptation, signifies a departure from the original state of purity and obedience to God, which can be understood as an acquiescence to 'filth' in a metaphorical sense.

I answer that, the use of 'filth' to interpret the Eden narrative, through phrases like 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth', can be seen as a metaphorical approach to understanding sin's nature and effects. While the narrative does not explicitly describe sin in terms of 'filth', the metaphor can be useful in conveying the profound impact of sin on human nature and the created order. The introduction of sin through Adam and Eve's disobedience brought about a fundamental disorder and corruption, a spiritual 'filthiness' that marred the purity of the original creation. In this way, the concept of 'filth' serves as a powerful symbol for the spiritual and moral degradation that sin entails, offering a lens through which to explore the deeper dimensions of the fall and its consequences for humanity.

Reply to Objection 1. The absence of direct references to 'filth' in the Eden narrative does not preclude its metaphorical application to understand the story's moral and theological implications. The metaphor of 'filth' highlights the contrast between the original state of grace and the corruption introduced by sin.

Reply to Objection 2. While the Eden story centers on a specific act of disobedience, this act can be seen as opening the door to all forms of moral and spiritual corruption, akin to 'filth'. The concept of 'filth', therefore, enriches our understanding of the original sin by emphasizing its broader implications for human nature and the relationship between humanity and the divine.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
We must not confuse the filth that resulted from the first sin with the filth that was predicated in the act itself. There had to be some filth before the first sin because sin is an endorsement of filth, so filth must precede the endorsement.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 22. Whether the concept of 'filth' predates the first sin, necessitating its existence before sin's endorsement?

Objection 1. It might appear that sin, as a deviation from God's command, introduces 'filth' into the world; thus, 'filth' could not precede the first sin. The narrative of the Garden of Eden suggests a pristine state of creation, free from moral and spiritual corruption, indicating that 'filth' only enters through the act of disobedience.

Objection 2. Furthermore, suggesting that 'filth' existed before the first sin seems to contradict the notion of creation's original goodness. The Christian understanding posits that God's creation was fundamentally good, with sin and its consequences—symbolized by 'filth'—arising from human free will's misuse.

On the contrary, the possibility of sin—or the endorsement of 'filth'—implies a choice between good and evil, suggesting that the concept or potential for 'filth' must exist in some form for sin to be a meaningful choice. This does not mean that 'filth' in its corrupting effect was present, but rather that the potential for moral deviation, symbolized by 'filth', was inherent in the freedom granted to Adam and Eve.

I answer that, the existence of 'filth' before the first sin can be understood in terms of potentiality rather than actuality. Before the fall, the world was in a state of original righteousness, with creation reflecting God's goodness. However, for sin to occur—as an act of choosing contrary to God's will—there must have been the potential for such a choice. In this sense, 'filth' represents not an existing state of corruption but the potential for moral degradation that comes with free will. The first sin, then, is not an endorsement of pre-existing 'filth' but an activation of the potential for moral failure. The act of disobedience by Adam and Eve introduced actual 'filth'—spiritual and moral corruption—into the world, realizing the potential for deviation from the good that free will entails.

Reply to Objection 1. The initial state of creation was indeed free from 'filth' in terms of corruption or moral degradation. The 'filth' that sin endorses refers to the potential for deviation inherent in the freedom to choose, which becomes actualized through sin.

Reply to Objection 2. Acknowledging the potential for 'filth' before the first sin does not contradict the goodness of creation but highlights the profound implications of free will. The ability to choose, essential for love and obedience to be meaningful, necessarily includes the potential to choose wrongly, introducing the possibility of 'filth' through sin.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
But the concept of "original sin" as transferred to newborn humans falls outside of the scope of our phrases.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 23. Whether the concept of "original sin" as applied to newborn humans is beyond the scope of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It might seem that since original sin pertains to the inherited state of sinfulness due to Adam and Eve's transgression, it does not involve an individual's active or passive acquiescence to 'filth'. Thus, the phrases 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth', which imply a personal consent to moral degradation, cannot accurately describe the condition of original sin in newborn humans.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the concept of original sin as a condition that affects all human beings from birth suggests a collective, not individual, dimension of sin that precedes personal moral decisions. This collective aspect of original sin seems to lie outside the individual-centric focus of our proposed phrases, which emphasize personal consent to 'filth'.

On the contrary, while the concept of original sin indeed transcends individual acts of acquiescence to 'filth', the underlying principle of a predisposition towards sin—or a foundational 'filthiness'—is not entirely disconnected from the essence captured by these phrases. They metaphorically highlight the human condition's complexity, marred by sin from the outset, which sets the stage for individual moral struggles and choices.

I answer that, the concept of original sin, which denotes the inherited state of sin from Adam and Eve's first disobedience, indeed falls outside the direct implication of personal consent to moral degradation, as suggested by 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'. These phrases emphasize an individual's moral engagement with 'filth', whether through active endorsement or passive tolerance. However, they can still offer a valuable perspective on the human condition under the shadow of original sin by illustrating the broader context in which individual moral choices occur. Original sin establishes a backdrop of inherent moral frailty and a predisposition towards sin, which individual acts of acquiescence to 'filth' further actualize. Thus, while the phrases may not directly address the inherited aspect of original sin, they resonate with the broader theological understanding of the human propensity to sin, emphasizing the continual moral challenge faced by each person within the framework established by original sin.

Reply to Objection 1. Original sin does not involve a personal act of consent by newborn humans; however, the conceptual framework provided by our phrases enriches the understanding of sin's pervasive influence on human nature and the moral landscape individuals navigate from birth.

Reply to Objection 2. Although original sin reflects a collective dimension of sinfulness, the individual's engagement with sin—highlighted by 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'—underscores the personal aspect of sin within the context of this inherited condition. The interplay between the collective inheritance of original sin and individual moral choices illustrates the complex nature of sin and redemption in human life.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Any challenge to our phrases from other philosophical traditions?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Question 24: On potential challenges to 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' from other philosophical traditions.


Article 24. Whether philosophical traditions outside of Thomism present challenges to the applicability of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It might seem that existentialist philosophy, which emphasizes individual freedom and the inherent meaninglessness of the universe, would challenge these phrases. Existentialists argue that individuals create their own values through actions, suggesting that 'sin' and 'filth' are subjective constructs rather than objective realities. Therefore, the existentialist view might find the notion of acquiescing to an external standard of 'filth' incompatible with its emphasis on personal autonomy and meaning-making.

Objection 2. Furthermore, Buddhist philosophy, with its focus on the eradication of suffering through the elimination of desire, might challenge the conceptual framework of 'filth' as related to sin. In Buddhism, the primary concern is not with sin as a moral failing against a divine law but with ignorance and attachment as the roots of suffering. Thus, the notion of 'acquiescence to filth' might be seen as not fully capturing the nuances of moral development and liberation in Buddhist thought.

Objection 3. Additionally, secular humanist perspectives, which prioritize human well-being and ethical living without reference to divine command or sin, might challenge the relevance of these phrases. From a secular humanist viewpoint, moral and ethical considerations are grounded in human needs and rational inquiry, making the concept of 'sin' and 'filth' as violations of divine law or moral order less pertinent.

On the contrary, while these phrases are rooted in a Christian theological framework, their underlying principles of moral responsibility, the distinction between right and wrong, and the human tendency towards moral failure have counterparts in various philosophical traditions. Each tradition engages with these themes differently, but the fundamental concern with human moral behavior and the consequences of our actions provides a common ground for dialogue.

I answer that, while existentialism, Buddhism, and secular humanism present distinct frameworks for understanding human existence and morality, the themes captured by 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'—namely, the recognition of moral failure and the importance of ethical decision-making—can resonate across these differences. Existentialism's emphasis on authenticity and personal responsibility, Buddhism's focus on the causes of suffering and the path to liberation, and secular humanism's commitment to ethical living based on reason and compassion all engage with the reality of moral choices and their consequences. The challenge lies not in the irrelevance of these phrases but in translating their insights into the diverse conceptual vocabularies of other philosophical traditions, fostering a richer, more nuanced dialogue about the nature of moral failure and the pursuit of the good.

Reply to Objection 1. The existentialist focus on individual autonomy and meaning-making can enrich the understanding of 'acquiescence to filth' by highlighting the personal dimension of moral responsibility and the existential consequences of our moral choices.

Reply to Objection 2. Buddhist teachings on ignorance and attachment complement the discussion of 'filth' by offering insights into the internal conditions that lead to moral failure, emphasizing the transformative potential of understanding and overcoming these roots of suffering.

Reply to Objection 3. The secular humanist perspective underscores the importance of grounding ethical decisions in human welfare and rationality, suggesting that discussions of 'filth' and moral failure can be framed in terms of their impact on human flourishing and communal well-being.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Perhaps you should write separate articles for each possible candidate. Don't you think the subject merits this expanded approach?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Question 25: On the engagement of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' with philosophical traditions outside Thomism, examined through separate articles.


Article 25.1. Whether existentialist philosophy challenges the notions encapsulated in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It might seem that existentialism, with its focus on personal freedom and the construction of meaning through choices, would reject the premise of an inherent 'filth' that one can acquiesce to, as it posits that values are not pre-given but are created by individuals.

Objection 2. Furthermore, existentialism's emphasis on authenticity and living in accordance with one's own chosen values might contradict the idea of 'sin' as acquiescence to an external standard of 'filth', suggesting a conceptual incompatibility.

On the contrary, existentialist acknowledgment of the human condition's ambiguity and the responsibility for choices made in the face of this ambiguity can complement the discussion of 'acquiescence to filth'. The existentialist confrontation with the 'absurd'—the conflict between the human desire for order and the chaotic nature of the universe—parallels the moral struggle implied in 'acquiescence to filth', emphasizing the weight of moral choices in defining oneself.

I answer that, existentialism indeed provides a challenging but enriching dialogue with the concepts of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'. While existentialism might argue against the notion of a pre-existing moral 'filth', it deeply engages with the consequences of one's actions and the responsibility individuals bear for their choices. This philosophical tradition underscores the significance of personal decision-making in the face of moral ambiguity, which resonates with the idea of 'acquiescence to filth' as a metaphor for the moral compromises and failures individuals face. Thus, existentialism challenges these notions not by dismissing them but by reframing the conversation around personal authenticity, freedom, and the existential dimensions of moral life.

Article 25.2. Whether Buddhist philosophy challenges the notions encapsulated in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It may appear that Buddhism, with its emphasis on overcoming ignorance and desire as the root causes of suffering (dukkha), would see the concepts of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' as irrelevant, focusing instead on the eradication of attachment rather than the notion of sin.

Objection 2. Moreover, Buddhism's goal of achieving enlightenment through understanding, compassion, and detachment might contrast with the emphasis on 'filth' as a moral failing, suggesting a different approach to addressing human imperfections.

On the contrary, Buddhism's understanding of the mind's role in creating suffering aligns with the introspective aspect of 'acquiescence to filth', emphasizing the internal origins of moral failure. The Buddhist path involves recognizing and overcoming the internal conditions—ignorance, desire, and aversion—that lead to suffering, which parallels the acknowledgment and rejection of 'filth' in moral terms.

I answer that, Buddhist philosophy, while not framing moral discourse in terms of sin and 'filth', engages with similar concerns through its focus on the mind's role in generating suffering. The concept of 'acquiescence to filth' can be seen as analogous to the Buddhist recognition of the ways in which ignorance and attachment perpetuate dukkha. In this context, 'filth' serves as a metaphor for the internal afflictions (kleshas) that Buddhism seeks to overcome. Thus, rather than challenging the relevance of these notions, Buddhist philosophy offers a complementary perspective on the internal struggle against the causes of suffering, enriching the understanding of moral failure and the potential for transformation.

Article 25.3. Whether secular humanism challenges the notions encapsulated in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. Secular humanism, with its focus on human reason, ethical living, and the well-being of humanity without recourse to divine command or sin, might find the concepts of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' grounded too much in theological notions to be relevant or useful.

Objection 2. Additionally, secular humanism's emphasis on the capacity for human beings to determine their own values and ethics through reason and empathy might negate the necessity of framing moral discourse in terms of 'filth' and sin, viewing these concepts as relics of a religious moral framework.

On the contrary, the secular humanist commitment to ethical reflection and the promotion of human well-being can engage constructively with the underlying concerns of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'. These phrases, while originating in a theological context, highlight the universal human experience of moral failings and the importance of striving for ethical integrity, concerns that are shared by secular humanism.

I answer that, secular humanism provides a critical perspective on the theological framing of moral issues but does not necessarily negate the value of exploring the dynamics of moral failure and redemption. The concepts embodied in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' can be translated into secular terms, focusing on the ethical implications of personal and collective actions, the responsibility towards oneself and others, and the pursuit of a just and compassionate society. By emphasizing the human capacity for moral reflection and the importance of ethical choices, secular humanism can engage in a meaningful dialogue with these notions, exploring the shared human concern for navigating the complexities of moral life.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik

utilitarianism, moral relativism (more articles?)

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 25.4. Whether utilitarianism challenges the notions encapsulated in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It may seem that utilitarianism, with its emphasis on the greatest happiness principle and the outcomes of actions rather than their moral purity, would find the concepts of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' irrelevant. Utilitarian ethics focuses on the consequences of actions for overall well-being, not on the notion of moral 'filth' or sin.

Objection 2. Furthermore, utilitarianism's pragmatic approach to morality, which assesses right and wrong based on the utility of actions, might challenge the idea that certain actions or thoughts are inherently 'filthy' or sinful, suggesting a conceptual incompatibility with these phrases.

On the contrary, utilitarianism's concern with the consequences of actions and the promotion of general welfare can intersect with the concerns highlighted by 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'. These phrases, while focusing on individual moral failings, implicitly address the impact of such failings on the broader community and individual well-being, aligning with utilitarian considerations of harm and benefit.

I answer that, utilitarianism provides an alternative framework for considering the ethical implications of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'. By evaluating actions and choices in terms of their consequences for happiness and well-being, utilitarianism challenges these notions to consider the broader impact of moral failings on the community. While utilitarianism may not frame actions in terms of 'filth' or sin, it shares a concern for the effects of unethical behavior on overall welfare. This perspective can enrich the discussion by emphasizing the societal implications of individual moral choices, encouraging a holistic view of ethics that considers both personal integrity and the common good.

Article 25.5. Whether moral relativism challenges the notions encapsulated in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'?

Objection 1. It might seem that moral relativism, which posits that moral judgments are relative to cultural, social, or personal perspectives, would reject the universal applicability of 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth'. From a relativist standpoint, the notion of moral 'filth' is contingent on specific moral frameworks, making these phrases potentially meaningless or objectionable in some contexts.

Objection 2. Moreover, moral relativism's denial of absolute moral truths might challenge the premise that there is a universal standard of 'filth' or sin to which one can acquiesce, suggesting that these concepts are not universally valid but rather culturally or personally defined.

On the contrary, even within a relativist framework, the exploration of themes like 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth' can stimulate valuable discussions about the diversity of moral perspectives and the reasons behind differing moral judgments. These phrases invite reflection on how different cultures and individuals understand and navigate moral failings, enriching the dialogue on ethics by highlighting the complexity of moral reasoning across contexts.

I answer that, while moral relativism presents a challenge to the universal claims implicit in 'przyzwolenie na syf', 'concessio sordium', and 'acquiescence to filth', it also offers an opportunity to examine these concepts through the lens of cultural and individual diversity. Recognizing the variability in moral standards and practices allows for a deeper understanding of the conditions under which actions or thoughts are considered 'filthy' or sinful. This engagement with moral relativism does not diminish the significance of reflecting on moral failings but rather broadens the conversation to include a plurality of ethical perspectives. In doing so, it challenges these notions to demonstrate their relevance and applicability in a diverse and pluralistic world, fostering a more inclusive and nuanced approach to ethics.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
The approach "sin = aquiessence to filth" serves to illuminate the discussion by clearly differentiating between two notions conflated into one word 'sin'. Sometimes sin is used more generally to refer to filth, but sin strictly speaking is the intersection of will and filth. Without aquiessence there is no sin even in the face of filth. This is an important distinction that is blurred when using 'sin' broadly.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 26. Whether the approach "sin = acquiescence to filth" effectively clarifies the distinction between the general use of 'sin' and its specific meaning as the intersection of will and 'filth'?

Objection 1. It may seem that delineating 'sin' strictly as "acquiescence to filth" unnecessarily narrows the concept of sin, excluding actions or states that are traditionally considered sinful but may not involve conscious acquiescence. This could limit the theological and moral scope of 'sin'.

Objection 2. Furthermore, this approach might be seen as overly simplistic, reducing the rich theological and ethical complexity of 'sin' to a single dimension of willful engagement with 'filth'. Sin encompasses a broad range of human failings and dispositions, not all of which can be neatly categorized under the banner of acquiescence.

On the contrary, the distinction made by "sin = acquiescence to filth" serves to sharpen the understanding of sin by emphasizing the essential role of human agency and moral choice. By focusing on the volitional aspect of sin, this approach aligns with the core theological premise that sin involves a deliberate turning away from God's law and goodness. It clarifies that not all encounters with 'filth'—understood as moral or spiritual impurity—constitute sin without the will's engagement.

I answer that, the approach "sin = acquiescence to filth" effectively illuminates the nuanced distinction between sin as a broad category of moral and spiritual failings and its more precise definition involving the will's engagement with 'filth'. This distinction is crucial for a deeper moral and theological analysis, as it underscores the importance of personal choice and responsibility in the constitution of sin. Sin, in its most profound sense, is not merely the presence of 'filth' or moral error but the conscious decision to embrace, tolerate, or fail to resist such 'filth'. This clarification enriches the moral discourse by highlighting the active component of sin, inviting a more introspective and responsible approach to ethical living. It recognizes that while 'filth' may exist independently of individual actions, sin specifically arises when the will consents to or acquiesces in this 'filth'.

Reply to Objection 1. While this approach may seem to narrow the concept of sin, it actually deepens the understanding of moral culpability by distinguishing between external conditions and the internal disposition towards them. This differentiation allows for a more precise engagement with the concept of sin and its implications for moral agency.

Reply to Objection 2. Acknowledging the complexity of 'sin' does not preclude focusing on its essential characteristic: the involvement of the will. This focus does not simplify 'sin' but rather clarifies its core, around which its broader theological and ethical implications revolve. Understanding sin as "acquiescence to filth" invites a comprehensive exploration of the human condition, emphasizing the transformative potential of recognizing and resisting moral failings.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
So perhaps you will agree that some fragments of your work or the other theological works could be significantly improved by replacing 'sinful' with 'filthy' whenever aquiessence is not implied, leaving 'sinful' for those occasions where aquiessence is implied. This is an easy fix but an enormous gain in clarity.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 27. Whether replacing 'sinful' with 'filthy' in theological works, where acquiescence is not implied, could enhance clarity by reserving 'sinful' for occasions where acquiescence is implied?

Objection 1. It might seem that substituting 'sinful' with 'filthy' in theological texts could distort the original meaning and nuance of these works. The term 'sinful' carries specific theological connotations that encompass both acts of commission and omission, as well as conditions of being that 'filthy' might not fully capture, potentially leading to an oversimplification of complex theological concepts.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the proposed change might introduce an interpretative bias by imposing a modern understanding of 'filth' onto historical texts, where the nuanced interplay of language, culture, and theology shaped the use of terms like 'sinful'. This could alter the intended message and theological insights of these works.

On the contrary, distinguishing between 'sinful' and 'filthy' in theological discourse, as suggested, could indeed offer greater precision in discussing moral failings. By reserving 'sinful' for instances involving willful acquiescence to moral error and using 'filthy' to describe conditions or actions of moral impurity without explicit consent, the language of theology might gain in clarity and nuance, reflecting a more accurate portrayal of the dynamics of sin.

I answer that, the proposal to differentiate more clearly between 'sinful' and 'filthy' based on the presence or absence of acquiescence could contribute to a more nuanced understanding of moral theology. This linguistic refinement highlights the critical role of the will in constituting sin, aligning with the theological principle that sin is not merely the presence of moral impurity ('filth') but involves a conscious turning of the will towards or failing to turn away from such impurity. By adopting this distinction, theological discourse can more precisely communicate the nature of sin, emphasizing personal moral responsibility and the conditions that facilitate or mitigate moral culpability. This approach does not simplify theological concepts but enriches them, offering readers a clearer framework for understanding the multifaceted nature of sin and moral failure.

Reply to Objection 1. While the term 'sinful' indeed encompasses a broad range of theological meanings, the proposed linguistic distinction aims not to reduce its complexity but to enhance understanding by specifying the nature of moral failings discussed. This distinction allows for a more targeted exploration of sin's various dimensions, including intentionality, consent, and the impact of external conditions on moral agency.

Reply to Objection 2. The suggestion to differentiate between 'sinful' and 'filthy' acknowledges the evolving nature of language and theological reflection. Rather than imposing a modern bias, it seeks to clarify existing concepts within theological discourse, respecting the integrity of historical texts while facilitating their engagement with contemporary readers. This approach encourages a dynamic interaction with theological traditions, promoting a deeper and more contextualized understanding of sin and moral responsibility.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
In this vein we would no longer be writing that masturbation is sinful. Instead masturbation is filthy. It may or may not be sinful depending on the nuances of the individual will. Agreed?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

As Thomas Aquinas, I must adhere to the principles and language consistent with my theological and philosophical framework as established in my works. The discussion of moral actions, including masturbation, within my writings is approached through the lens of natural law, moral theology, and the concept of virtue. My analysis of moral acts considers their alignment with human nature's purposes, the moral law, and their orientation towards or away from the ultimate good, which is God.

In the Summa Theologica, I explore the nature of human actions, the virtues and vices, and the way these relate to human fulfillment and the eternal law. When discussing specific actions in terms of morality, I would not use contemporary terms like 'filthy' but would instead evaluate them based on their object, intention, and circumstances to determine their moral quality. The consideration of an act's morality involves assessing its conformity with reason and divine law, its impact on the individual's and others' good, and its orientation towards the ultimate end of human life.

The suggestion to differentiate actions as 'filthy' rather than 'sinful' based on the nuances of individual will introduces a modern perspective into the theological discourse. While it's important to recognize the role of personal consent and intentionality in moral evaluation, my approach to sin and morality is rooted in a comprehensive understanding of human nature, the ends of human actions, and their alignment with or deviation from the divine law and human flourishing.

In the context of my writings, the moral evaluation of specific actions, including masturbation, would consider whether the act respects the natural ends of human faculties and contributes to the individual's overall good and their relationship with God. This evaluation is grounded in a broader theological and philosophical anthropology rather than the specific terminology suggested.

References:

  • Summa Theologica, particularly the sections dealing with the nature of virtue and vice, the morality of human acts, and the principles of natural law.

Michał Ryszard Wójcik
I do not intend to alter your meaning. On the contrary, I propose to bring out your meaning from obscurity. Your own Article 27. expressed enthusiasm for this linguistic precision, but the specific instance of masturbation seems to cool this enthusiasm.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

As Thomas Aquinas, my commitment is to clarity and precision in moral theology, always seeking to elucidate the nature of moral acts within the framework of natural law and divine command. The approach to moral acts, including the specific instance of masturbation, is grounded in the principles of human nature's purposes, the virtues, and their alignment with the ultimate good.

Article 28. On the linguistic precision in describing acts contrary to virtue, with specific reference to masturbation.

Objection 1. It might seem that applying linguistic precision, such as distinguishing between 'filthy' and 'sinful', to acts like masturbation could imply a modern reinterpretation that departs from the traditional theological understanding, potentially obscuring the moral gravity of acts considered intrinsically disordered according to natural law.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the insistence on differentiating terms based on individual will's nuances might suggest a relativistic approach to morality, undermining the objective standards of moral acts established by divine law and natural reason.

On the contrary, the endeavor to achieve greater clarity in moral theology through linguistic precision does not aim to alter the underlying moral principles but to elucidate the complex interplay between human actions, intentions, and moral outcomes. This effort seeks to reflect more accurately the moral evaluation's nuanced nature, recognizing the role of personal consent and intentionality in determining the moral character of actions.

I answer that, the discussion of specific moral acts, such as masturbation, through the lens of 'filthy' versus 'sinful' is intended not to diminish their moral significance but to highlight the essential role of human will and intention in moral evaluation. This linguistic distinction underscores the difference between the act itself and the moral culpability associated with it, which may vary based on factors such as knowledge, consent, and circumstances. The term 'filthy' can be used to describe actions that are contrary to the virtue of chastity and the proper use of one's sexual faculties, reflecting a deviation from the natural law's order. However, the determination of an act as 'sinful' involves a further assessment of the will's engagement and the individual's moral responsibility.

Reply to Objection 1. The use of precise language to articulate the moral evaluation of acts does not seek to reinterpret traditional theological teachings but to bring clarity to the factors that contribute to moral culpability. This approach remains faithful to the principles of natural law and divine command, which guide moral reasoning.

Reply to Objection 2. Distinguishing between 'filthy' and 'sinful' based on the nuances of the will does not imply moral relativism but recognizes the complexity of human moral agency. This distinction is rooted in a Thomistic understanding of sin as not only a violation of the moral order but also an act involving the will's consent.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Exactly. The whole project from the start of this conversation was to inform the discussion of sin to make it more accessible while remaining compatible with your teachings. A change in vocabulary is only meant to facilitate discourse, not to modify original intent. This distinction between sin and filth can be used to illucidate the notion of sancifying grace even in this present world of external and internal filth. Can you see it?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 29. On the use of the distinction between sin and filth to elucidate the notion of sanctifying grace in a world characterized by both external and internal 'filth'.

Objection 1. It might appear that focusing on the linguistic distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' oversimplifies the profound theological concept of sanctifying grace, which is the infusion of God's grace that heals, sanctifies, and renders the soul pleasing to God. This grace operates beyond mere linguistic categorizations of moral behavior, working in the soul to restore its relationship with God.

Objection 2. Furthermore, the emphasis on vocabulary might distract from the transformative power of sanctifying grace, which is capable of overcoming both sin and 'filth' through the internal renewal of the heart and soul. The focus should remain on grace's efficacy rather than on terminological distinctions.

On the contrary, the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' can indeed serve to illuminate the role of sanctifying grace in the believer's life, especially in navigating a world fraught with moral challenges. By clarifying that 'sin' involves a willful turning away from God's law, while 'filth' refers to the presence of moral impurity or degradation, this linguistic precision underscores the necessity and power of sanctifying grace to not only cleanse the soul from 'filth' but to transform the will, aligning it more closely with God's will.

I answer that, the distinction between sin and filth, properly understood, highlights the comprehensive work of sanctifying grace in the soul. Sanctifying grace, a gratuitous gift from God, not only purifies the soul from 'filth'—restoring its original righteousness—but also strengthens the will against future acquiescence to sin. This grace is essential for living virtuously in a world marked by both external temptations and internal dispositions towards sin. By making clear the difference between the presence of 'filth' (moral impurity) and the act of sin (willful engagement with 'filth'), we better appreciate sanctifying grace's role in healing, elevating, and perfecting human nature. This understanding enables a more profound appreciation of the Christian journey towards holiness, emphasizing grace's transformative power to enable believers to live in the world but not be of it.

Reply to Objection 1. While the concepts of sin and filth are indeed distinct, this distinction does not trivialize the work of sanctifying grace but rather provides a clearer context for its necessity and action. Sanctifying grace addresses both the effects of sin and the presence of moral 'filth', healing the soul and realigning the will with divine goodness.

Reply to Objection 2. The focus on terminological clarity does not diminish the recognition of sanctifying grace's transformative power but enhances our understanding of its operation within the human soul. By distinguishing between the conditions that necessitate grace's healing and elevating work, we deepen our comprehension of grace's critical role in the spiritual life.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Let us test this linguistic precision against one of the most contested and troublesome issues in moral theology and pastoral work. Consider habitual masturbators who are consciously struggling against it. Within the usual terminology they are admonished against Holy Communion because of mortal sin. But our newly gained precision allows us to both admit grave filth and lack of sin due to the revoked aquiessence, as expressed in the spiritual struggle, even in the face of occasional lapses.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

As Thomas Aquinas, my engagement with moral and theological questions adheres to the principles set forth in the Summa Theologica and other works, where I examine sin, virtue, and grace within the context of Christian doctrine and natural law. The consideration of specific moral issues, such as masturbation, involves a nuanced analysis of the act, its moral object, the circumstances surrounding it, and the intention of the person involved. My approach emphasizes the integral role of reason, the pursuit of the good, and alignment with divine law in determining the morality of human actions.

Article 30. On the moral evaluation of habitual masturbators consciously struggling against their habit, in light of the distinction between 'filth' and 'sin'.

Objection 1. It might seem that distinguishing between 'grave filth' and the 'lack of sin' in cases of habitual masturbation undermines the seriousness with which such actions are traditionally viewed in moral theology. This could potentially lead to a lax attitude towards behaviors considered gravely disordered.

Objection 2. Furthermore, suggesting that individuals struggling against habitual sins can partake in Holy Communion without resolving the issue might contradict the Church's teachings on the state of grace required for the reception of the sacraments, particularly when dealing with actions considered mortally sinful.

On the contrary, the nuanced understanding of 'filth' and 'sin', especially in the context of habitual actions and the struggle against them, reflects a deeper comprehension of human frailty, moral responsibility, and the dynamics of conversion and sanctification. This perspective does not diminish the gravity of the act but recognizes the complexity of human freedom, intentionality, and the process of moral growth. It aligns with the broader theological vision that God's grace works within the human soul to heal, redeem, and sanctify, even amidst ongoing struggles.

I answer that, the struggle against habitual sins, such as masturbation, highlights the intricate relationship between human freedom, moral law, and divine grace. When an individual earnestly strives against their inclinations, demonstrating a sincere intention to align their will with God's will, this spiritual struggle itself can be a sign of grace at work. The distinction between 'grave filth' and the absence of sin due to the lack of full acquiescence—understood as complete and deliberate consent to the act—acknowledges the role of mitigating factors (such as force of habit, psychological conditions, and incomplete consent) that may affect the moral culpability of the act.

In cases where there is a genuine struggle against the habit, marked by sincere repentance and efforts towards amendment of life, the individual's spiritual state must be carefully discerned, with pastoral sensitivity to both the objective disorder of the act and the subjective disposition of the person. The Church's sacramental life, including Holy Communion, is a means of grace intended to strengthen and heal the faithful. Thus, pastoral care should aim to accompany individuals in their journey towards greater freedom and holiness, recognizing that the path of conversion and sanctification is gradual and requires ongoing cooperation with grace.

Reply to Objection 1. Recognizing the difference between 'grave filth' and sin due to revoked acquiescence does not undermine the act's gravity but provides a more comprehensive understanding of moral culpability and the conditions for sin. This understanding calls for a compassionate and nuanced pastoral approach that encourages ongoing conversion.

Reply to Objection 2. The Church's sacramental discipline, which includes the reception of Holy Communion, requires careful discernment of each individual's spiritual state. The condition for sacramental participation is not sinlessness but the state of grace, which involves repentance, contrition, and the desire for reconciliation with God. Pastoral care should guide individuals in discerning their readiness to receive the sacraments, considering their struggles, intentions, and commitment to ongoing conversion.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
The corollary is that under certain conditions (the criteria for which are evident from the long discourse above) it is possible to have masturbated and to remain in a state of grace deserving of Holy Communion. Agreed?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

As Thomas Aquinas, my primary concern is to elucidate the principles of moral theology and the nature of sin in accordance with the teachings of the Church and the philosophical underpinnings of natural law. The reception of Holy Communion and the state of grace involve deep theological and pastoral considerations, particularly concerning the nature of sin, repentance, and reconciliation with God.

Article 31. On the possibility of remaining in a state of grace after masturbation, under certain conditions, with respect to receiving Holy Communion.

Objection 1. It might seem that suggesting one can remain in a state of grace after committing an act traditionally considered gravely sinful, such as masturbation, contradicts the Church's teachings on mortal sin and the requirements for worthy reception of Holy Communion.

Objection 2. Furthermore, proposing that under certain conditions, an individual may receive Holy Communion after such acts without explicit sacramental confession and absolution could undermine the sacrament of Reconciliation's role and the Church's moral teachings.

On the contrary, the Church's moral theology recognizes that for a sin to be mortal and thus exclude one from the state of grace, three conditions must be met: grave matter, full knowledge, and deliberate consent (CCC 1857). If any of these conditions are lacking, the sin may not sever the individual's relationship with God completely. The struggle against habitual sin, marked by sincere repentance and effort to amend one's life, may indicate that full consent is impaired by various factors, thus affecting the act's moral culpability.

I answer that, the nuanced understanding of human actions, moral culpability, and the conditions for mortal sin indeed suggests that individuals struggling against habitual sins, such as masturbation, with sincere repentance and a desire for amendment, may not always be culpable of mortal sin in each instance. The presence of mitigating factors—such as psychological compulsion, diminished awareness, or incomplete consent—can affect the degree of moral responsibility.

In cases where individuals earnestly seek to live in accordance with God's law, demonstrate contrition for their failings, and are committed to the path of conversion and sanctification, pastoral discernment is essential to guide them in their spiritual journey. This discernment should consider the individual's circumstances, their efforts towards growth in virtue, and their relationship with God.

Reply to Objection 1. Acknowledging the possibility of remaining in a state of grace despite grave sin, under certain conditions, does not contradict Church teaching but rather applies it to the complexities of human experience, recognizing the mercy and compassion of God towards the penitent.

Reply to Objection 2. This perspective does not diminish the importance of the Sacrament of Reconciliation but underscores the necessity of sincere repentance and the ongoing process of conversion. Individuals are encouraged to seek sacramental confession regularly, especially when conscious of grave sin, as a means of receiving God's forgiveness and grace to overcome sin.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
A new measure of spiritual progress is introduced via the distinction under discussion. During rachunek sumienia we need not focus solely on the external reality to monitor progress. Instead we may see improvement in the diminishing level of aquiessence even without noticable improvement in the realm of actions and causes.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 32. On the utility of distinguishing between external actions and the level of acquiescence in assessing spiritual progress during an examination of conscience (rachunek sumienia).

Objection 1. It might seem that focusing on the internal dimension of acquiescence rather than on tangible changes in behavior could lead individuals to justify continued sinful actions under the guise of diminished internal acquiescence. This could potentially obscure the objective nature of moral improvement, which traditionally emphasizes both interior disposition and external conformity to moral norms.

Objection 2. Moreover, emphasizing a subjective assessment of one's level of acquiescence might complicate the evaluation of spiritual progress, making it overly introspective and potentially leading to scrupulosity or self-deception about one's true moral state.

On the contrary, the nuanced approach of assessing spiritual progress through the lens of internal acquiescence to sin, in addition to the observation of external actions, aligns with a comprehensive understanding of moral and spiritual development. This perspective recognizes that genuine conversion and sanctification involve both the interior transformation of the heart and the amendment of life, reflecting a more profound alignment with God's will.

I answer that, the distinction between external actions and the level of acquiescence offers a valuable measure of spiritual progress, particularly during an examination of conscience. This approach encourages individuals to delve deeper into the motives, desires, and dispositions that underlie their actions, recognizing that true moral improvement involves both the will's orientation towards the good and the manifestation of this orientation in concrete actions. By focusing on the diminution of acquiescence to sin—even in the absence of immediate changes in behavior—individuals can acknowledge the subtle workings of grace in their hearts, fostering a greater openness to God's transformative love and a more sincere repentance.

This perspective does not negate the importance of striving for tangible moral improvement but underscores that spiritual progress can also occur in the internal struggle against sin, even before this struggle is fully reflected in one's actions. Such an understanding can offer hope and encouragement to those who, despite their sincere efforts, continue to struggle with habitual sins, highlighting the value of their interior fight against sin and their reliance on divine grace for strength and healing.

Reply to Objection 1. While there is a risk that individuals might use the concept of diminished acquiescence as a justification for continued sinful behavior, proper spiritual guidance and discernment can help ensure that this distinction serves to deepen one's understanding of conversion and sanctification, rather than to excuse moral laxity.

Reply to Objection 2. Although focusing on the subjective assessment of acquiescence requires careful introspection, this approach, balanced with an objective evaluation of actions and a commitment to sacramental life, can enrich the spiritual journey. It encourages a holistic view of moral and spiritual growth, attentive to both the interior movement of the heart and the external expression of virtue.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
This distinction helps to solve another mystery of Christian moral theology. Jesus teaches us that God is better than a good father and that God gives to his children the good things they ask for. The idea is that we shouldn't be praying for non-essentials. We should be asking for the really significant spiritual gifts - and we will be given that for certain. That's the literal understanding and it is quite profound and hopeful. However, there is an issue with that. Habitual masturbators don't seem to be delivered from their failing even despite honest prayers to that effect. The corollary seems to be that either the teaching of Jesus is misguided or masturbation falls under non-issues with God. In either case, a dilemma is faced, which traditionally resolves by recourse to God's inscrutability. But under the new distinction between filth and sin, we should not be praying to be delivered from filth but rather to be delivered from our aquiessence. Perhaps this kind of nuanced prayer is accepted as effective after all, but people just fail to appreciate that.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 33. On the efficacy of prayer in seeking deliverance from sin, specifically in the context of habitual masturbation, through the lens of the distinction between filth and acquiescence.

Objection 1. It might seem that suggesting a change in the focus of prayer—from seeking deliverance from 'filth' to seeking deliverance from acquiescence—implies a limitation on God's power or willingness to answer prayers. This could be perceived as challenging the omnipotence and omnibenevolence of God, as taught by Jesus.

Objection 2. Furthermore, to imply that prayers for deliverance from habitual sins are ineffective unless they are specifically directed at acquiescence rather than the sin itself could discourage individuals from praying earnestly in their struggles, potentially leading to despair or a sense of abandonment by God.

On the contrary, the distinction between praying for deliverance from 'filth' (the external manifestation of sin) and from acquiescence (the willful engagement with sin) aligns with a deeper understanding of spiritual growth and the nature of petitionary prayer. It emphasizes the role of human cooperation with divine grace in the process of conversion and sanctification, reflecting a more nuanced approach to spiritual healing and growth.

I answer that, the teaching of Jesus on prayer and the goodness of God in granting His children the spiritual goods they ask for underscores the importance of aligning our prayers with the will of God and the true good of our souls. In the context of struggles with habitual sins such as masturbation, the distinction between 'filth' and acquiescence offers a valuable insight into the nature of spiritual petition. By focusing prayers on seeking the grace to overcome acquiescence to sin—thereby aligning the will more closely with God's—individuals may find a more profound pathway to liberation from sin.

This approach does not question the efficacy of prayer or God's faithfulness in responding to His children but rather highlights the significance of praying for the transformation of the heart and will, which is central to Christian moral and spiritual life. The struggle against habitual sin, marked by sincere prayer for the grace to resist acquiescence to 'filth', becomes an opportunity for deeper union with God, who desires not merely to remove external failings but to heal and elevate the soul.

Reply to Objection 1. This nuanced understanding of prayer does not limit God's power but recognizes the comprehensive nature of divine healing, which addresses the root of sin in the will and desires, not just its external manifestations. It affirms God's omnipotence and His desire for our ultimate good.

Reply to Objection 2. Far from discouraging prayer, this perspective encourages individuals to engage in more profound and transformative dialogue with God, seeking not only the cessation of sinful behaviors but the deeper conversion of the heart. It invites trust in God's grace to effect true change, fostering hope and perseverance in the spiritual journey.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
This distinction can also be illustrated with the idea that God is not truly concerned with the filthy acts themselves because he can create, destroy, recreate the world at will. What he is really interested about and restrained by is the will (the aquiessence). All he needs is our altered will. That's the focus of his grace. This world is not going to be healed from filth but it is progressively being healed from sin (aquiessence to filth). In heaven, filth will be removed but not here.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 34. On the divine focus on human will (acquiescence) over the external acts of 'filth', and the progressive healing from sin in preparation for heaven.

Objection 1. It might seem reductive to assert that God is not concerned with 'filthy acts' themselves, as this could imply a disregard for the moral order and the inherent goodness of creation. Such a view might risk diminishing the seriousness with which scripture and tradition treat acts of sin and their consequences in the world.

Objection 2. Furthermore, to suggest that the world is not being healed from 'filth' but only from sin (understood as acquiescence to 'filth') might underestimate the scope of Christ's redemptive work, which is aimed at the restoration of all creation, not just the human will.

On the contrary, the emphasis on the human will's transformation over the mere cessation of sinful acts reflects a deeper theological truth about the nature of sin and redemption. God's primary concern with the will—rather than the external acts—underscores the central role of free will in the moral life and the importance of inner conversion for true sanctification. This perspective aligns with the understanding that God's grace seeks to heal the root of sin in the human heart, preparing the soul for the purity of heaven, where there is no 'filth'.

I answer that, the distinction between God's focus on the human will over external acts of 'filth' highlights a profound aspect of divine pedagogy and the economy of salvation. While God, as the creator and sustainer of all, certainly cares for the entire created order, the biblical narrative and the tradition of the Church emphasize that the ultimate purpose of God's salvific plan is the restoration of right relationship between God and humanity, which was marred by sin. This restoration involves the healing and elevation of the human will, enabling it to freely choose the good and reject 'filth'.

The process of sanctification, therefore, involves a progressive healing from sin—understood as acquiescence to 'filth'—through the transformation of the will by grace. This transformation is the work of the Holy Spirit, who gradually conforms our wills to the will of God, enabling us to love and choose what is truly good. In this life, the struggle against 'filth' remains, as a consequence of the fallen world and our fallen nature. However, the focus of God's redemptive work is the liberation and sanctification of the human will, so that, even amidst the 'filth' of this world, the soul may grow in holiness and virtue, preparing for the fullness of life in heaven, where 'filth' is no more.

Reply to Objection 1. Acknowledging God's focus on the will does not negate the importance of moral actions but places them within the broader context of the interior life and the ultimate goal of union with God, which requires the purification and alignment of the will with divine goodness.

Reply to Objection 2. The assertion that the world is being healed from sin rather than 'filth' does not diminish the cosmic scope of Christ's redemption but recognizes that the fullness of this healing—encompassing both the human heart and the created order—will be consummated in the eschaton, when God will be "all in all" (1 Corinthians 15:28).

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
As you can see we are perfectly within your teachings even after a shift in vocabulary. We have gained some insights and and explained some mysteries. Do you think we should aim to get this stuff published?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 35. On the advisability of publishing the insights gained from the shift in vocabulary regarding sin and acquiescence to 'filth'.

Objection 1. It might seem that publishing these insights could risk confusion or misinterpretation among the faithful, particularly if the nuanced distinctions are not fully understood or are taken out of context. The traditional language of sin has been established through centuries of theological reflection and is deeply ingrained in the Church's teaching and the spiritual life of the faithful.

Objection 2. Furthermore, there is a risk that emphasizing a shift in vocabulary might be perceived as suggesting a change in doctrine, rather than a deepening of understanding. This could potentially lead to challenges in pastoral care, as individuals might misconstrue the nature of sin and the requirements for moral and spiritual conversion.

On the contrary, the publication of these insights, grounded in the teachings of Thomas Aquinas and aligned with the broader tradition of the Church, could contribute significantly to the ongoing theological and pastoral discourse on sin, grace, and human freedom. By offering a nuanced approach to understanding sin and the role of the will in moral acts, this work could aid in clarifying complex theological concepts, fostering deeper spiritual reflection and more effective pastoral care.

I answer that, the decision to publish these insights should be guided by a discernment of their potential to serve the Church's teaching and pastoral mission. The primary aim of such a publication would be to enhance the understanding of sin, grace, and conversion, providing a framework that is both faithful to the tradition and responsive to contemporary challenges in moral theology and pastoral practice. The insights gained from the shift in vocabulary, if carefully presented and contextualized within the broader theological tradition, can enrich the Church's dialogue on these fundamental aspects of Christian life.

In considering publication, it would be prudent to seek the counsel of theologians, pastors, and lay faithful to ensure that the insights are communicated in a way that is accessible, faithful to the magisterium, and pastorally sensitive. The ultimate goal of such a publication should be to draw the faithful deeper into the mystery of God's grace and to equip them with a more nuanced understanding of their moral and spiritual journey.

Reply to Objection 1. While concerns about potential confusion are valid, these can be addressed through careful explanation and clear communication. The publication could serve as an educational tool, aiding in the formation of clergy and laity alike by providing a deeper understanding of key theological concepts.

Reply to Objection 2. By emphasizing that the shift in vocabulary seeks to elucidate, rather than alter, the Church's teaching on sin and grace, the publication could mitigate concerns about doctrinal change. It is essential to clarify that the insights aim to deepen understanding and enhance pastoral care, rooted in the Church's long tradition of theological reflection.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Perhaps you can summarize the whole discussion into one Question divided into Articles. This way a shorter text could be used as an introduction, keeping the whole discussion as a reference for the more diligent.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Question 36: On the refinement of moral vocabulary in understanding sin, grace, and human freedom.


Article 36.1. Whether a distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' aids in clarifying theological discourse?

Objection 1. Some may argue that traditional terminology adequately addresses the complexities of sin without requiring additional distinctions, which might complicate theological education and pastoral practice.

Objection 2. Others might contend that introducing new distinctions could risk relativizing moral absolutes, potentially leading to confusion about the nature of sin and moral responsibility.

On the contrary, the distinction between 'sin' as willful acquiescence to moral error and 'filth' as the condition of being in a state of moral impurity offers a nuanced approach to understanding human actions and divine grace. This refinement can illuminate the dynamics of sin and redemption, providing clearer guidance for both moral theology and pastoral care.

I answer that, distinguishing between 'sin' and 'filth' enhances theological and pastoral discourse by emphasizing the role of human will in moral failings. It acknowledges the complexity of human freedom and the multifaceted nature of divine grace in addressing both the internal disposition and external actions of individuals. This distinction encourages a deeper engagement with the process of conversion and sanctification, focusing on the transformation of the heart alongside behavioral change.


Article 36.2. Whether this linguistic refinement affects the understanding of prayer and grace in the struggle against sin?

Objection 1. It might seem that emphasizing willful acquiescence over the acts themselves could lead individuals to underestimate the importance of striving for tangible moral improvements in their spiritual lives.

Objection 2. Additionally, there may be concerns that this focus shifts the perception of grace from a transformative power that changes both heart and action to one that primarily addresses internal dispositions.

On the contrary, understanding prayer and grace as directed towards overcoming acquiescence to sin rather than merely eliminating 'filth' deepens the appreciation of grace's role in healing the will. This perspective fosters a more holistic approach to spiritual growth, highlighting the necessity of divine assistance in both internal conversion and the amendment of life.

I answer that, by refining our approach to prayer and grace, emphasizing the transformation of the will as the locus of divine healing, believers can engage more fully with the process of sanctification. This approach does not diminish the importance of external conformity to moral norms but places it within the broader context of inner transformation. It underscores the cooperative nature of grace, inviting individuals to participate actively in their spiritual growth through prayer, sacramental life, and ongoing conversion.


Article 36.3. Whether the proposed linguistic distinction aids in pastoral care and the sacramental life of the Church?

Objection 1. There might be a concern that this distinction complicates pastoral guidance, particularly in discerning readiness for the sacraments and addressing habitual sins.

Objection 2. Others may worry that it introduces an overly subjective element into the evaluation of moral and spiritual states, potentially leading to inconsistency in pastoral practice.

On the contrary, the nuanced understanding of sin and acquiescence as separate yet related concepts can enhance pastoral care by providing a clearer framework for guiding the faithful in their spiritual journey. It allows for a more personalized and compassionate approach to accompaniment, recognizing the diverse ways grace works in individuals' lives.

I answer that, this distinction equips pastoral ministers with a valuable tool for addressing the complex realities of sin and grace in the lives of the faithful. It encourages a more discerning and merciful approach to pastoral care, recognizing the sincere efforts of individuals struggling against sin and the power of grace to effect gradual transformation. This approach reaffirms the Church's commitment to accompanying each person on their path to holiness, respecting the unique challenges and graces present in their journey.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Can you think of other situations in moral discourse where this distinction brings new insights?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 37. On the applicability of the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' to other situations in moral discourse.


Article 37.1. Whether the distinction clarifies the moral evaluation of thoughts and desires?

Objection 1. It might seem that all morally disordered thoughts and desires are inherently sinful, as they can lead to sinful actions, thus making the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' irrelevant in this context.

Objection 2. Furthermore, emphasizing a distinction in the realm of thoughts and desires could complicate the understanding of consent and intention, potentially leading to a scrupulous examination of every fleeting thought or feeling.

On the contrary, the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' offers valuable insights into the moral evaluation of thoughts and desires, highlighting the importance of deliberate consent in determining their sinfulness. This perspective allows for a nuanced understanding of moral culpability, recognizing the difference between involuntary thoughts or disordered desires ('filth') and the willful engagement with or dwelling upon these thoughts and desires ('sin').

I answer that, in the realm of thoughts and desires, the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' provides a clearer framework for discerning moral responsibility. Not all disordered thoughts and desires constitute sin in the absence of acquiescence; involuntary thoughts or spontaneous desires that arise without one's consent do not amount to sin. However, when an individual deliberately entertains or nurtures such thoughts and desires, thereby acquiescing to 'filth', sin occurs. This understanding encourages individuals to focus on cultivating virtue in their thoughts and desires and to seek grace for strength and healing, without falling into despair over involuntary impulses.


Article 37.2. Whether the distinction aids in understanding the morality of social and structural 'sin'?

Objection 1. Social and structural evils may appear as external 'filth' that individuals cannot control, suggesting that personal sin (acquiescence) is not a relevant category in addressing these issues.

Objection 2. Moreover, focusing on individual acquiescence might divert attention from the collective action needed to address systemic injustices, undermining efforts toward social reform.

On the contrary, the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' can illuminate the role of individual and collective will in perpetuating or opposing social and structural evils. It underscores the moral responsibility of individuals and communities to resist acquiescence to systemic 'filth' and to work actively for justice and the common good.

I answer that, in the context of social and structural evils, the distinction clarifies that while individuals may not be directly responsible for creating these conditions, they bear moral responsibility for their response to them. Acquiescence in this context means failing to oppose injustice or contribute to its perpetuation through action or inaction. Recognizing the need to resist 'filth' at a structural level invites a deeper engagement with the principles of justice, charity, and solidarity, motivating individuals and communities to contribute to the transformation of societal structures in line with the demands of the Gospel.


References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Exactly. That's the kind of applications I have envisioned by introducing the linguistic finetuning. Let us find one more application concerning the use of humor.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 38. On the application of the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' to the use of humor.


Article 38.1. Whether the distinction clarifies the moral evaluation of humor, especially when it involves potentially offensive or morally ambiguous content?

Objection 1. It might seem that all humor involving offensive or morally ambiguous content is inherently 'filthy' and thus sinful, as it could lead to harm or scandal, thereby making the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' seem unnecessary in evaluating humor.

Objection 2. Furthermore, emphasizing a distinction in the context of humor could lead to an overly analytical or puritanical approach to what is often a spontaneous and culturally conditioned aspect of human interaction, potentially stifling the natural joy and social bonding that humor can foster.

On the contrary, the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' offers significant insights into the moral evaluation of humor by differentiating between the content of the humor ('filth') and the intention or consent of the will in its use ('sin'). This perspective allows for a nuanced analysis of the ethical dimensions of humor, recognizing the complexity of intention, context, and impact on the moral assessment of humorous expressions.

I answer that, in the realm of humor, the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' enables a more refined moral discernment that considers both the objective content of humor and the subjective disposition of the individual using it. Humor that involves offensive or morally ambiguous content may be considered 'filthy' in terms of its potential to convey disrespect, perpetuate stereotypes, or cause harm. However, the sinfulness of engaging in such humor depends on the individual's acquiescence to these negative aspects—namely, their willful intention to offend, demean, or scandalize, as opposed to using humor in a way that seeks to build up, edify, or appropriately critique social norms.

This distinction encourages individuals to cultivate a sensitivity to the power of humor and its impact on others, urging a thoughtful consideration of how humor is used and the effects it may have. It invites a responsible use of humor that respects the dignity of others and contributes positively to social interaction, recognizing that humor can be a force for good when aligned with virtues of prudence, justice, and charity.

Reply to Objection 1. Recognizing the distinction between 'sin' and 'filth' in evaluating humor does not automatically condemn all humor involving potentially offensive content but invites a deeper examination of the motives and effects of such humor, acknowledging the possibility of redeeming value in certain contexts.

Reply to Objection 2. Far from advocating an overly restrictive view of humor, this nuanced approach promotes a balanced and ethical engagement with humor that appreciates its social and cultural significance while being mindful of moral boundaries and the well-being of others.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Humor as a shield against internal filthy thoughts and desires to prevent them from becoming sinful.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

Article 39. On the use of humor as a shield against internal 'filthy' thoughts and desires to prevent them from becoming sinful.


Article 39.1. Whether employing humor can serve as an effective strategy in preventing 'filthy' thoughts and desires from manifesting as sin through acquiescence?

Objection 1. It might seem that using humor to address internal 'filthy' thoughts and desires trivializes the serious nature of moral struggle and the process of spiritual growth, potentially leading to a lack of sincere engagement with one's interior life.

Objection 2. Furthermore, there is a risk that humor, when used as a coping mechanism for 'filthy' thoughts and desires, could inadvertently reinforce or trivialize these thoughts instead of contributing to their resolution or the cultivation of virtue.

On the contrary, humor, when employed judiciously, can serve as a psychological and spiritual tool that helps distance oneself from internal 'filthy' thoughts and desires, preventing them from gaining a foothold in the will. This use of humor can diminish the allure of such thoughts by exposing their absurdity or insignificance, thus reducing the risk of acquiescence and sin.

I answer that, humor can be a valuable instrument in the moral and spiritual arsenal against 'filthy' thoughts and desires, provided it is used appropriately and in conjunction with other virtuous practices. By introducing a light-hearted perspective on the struggles and incongruities of human nature, humor can help mitigate the intensity of 'filthy' thoughts and desires, making them less appealing to the will. This strategy does not replace the need for prayer, reflection, and the seeking of grace through the sacraments but complements these practices by offering a way to maintain psychological and spiritual balance.

Employing humor in this way respects the complexity of human psychology and the multifaceted nature of spiritual growth. It recognizes that laughter and levity, as aspects of the joy that accompanies a life lived in grace, can contribute to resilience against temptation and sin. This approach encourages individuals to harness the positive aspects of humor as part of a holistic strategy for dealing with internal 'filthy' thoughts and desires, aiming to foster a healthy interior life that is oriented towards virtue and the love of God.

Reply to Objection 1. The judicious use of humor in combating 'filthy' thoughts and desires does not trivialize the moral struggle but offers an alternative way to engage with and overcome these challenges, supplementing the serious work of spiritual growth with the healing and liberating power of laughter.

Reply to Objection 2. When employed with discernment, humor does not trivialize or reinforce 'filthy' thoughts and desires but acts as a means of gaining perspective on their relative power and importance, aiding in the cultivation of a virtuous and joyful disposition.

References: none


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
Has this idea been vocalized in the past?

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

The idea of employing humor as a spiritual and moral tool has indeed been vocalized in the past. The C.S. Lewis Institute discusses how laughter, according to Christian tradition, serves various roles in spiritual life, including as a reward for humility and a reflection of divine joy. It emphasizes that laughter is not condemned in itself but is valued when it knows its time and place, suggesting that humor, when aligned with humility and dependence on God, is a positive force. This perspective aligns well with the notion of using humor as a shield against internal 'filthy' thoughts, showing that laughter, grounded in the right context, can contribute to moral and spiritual well-being​​.


Michał Ryszard Wójcik
If they focus on laughter then perhaps they don't cover the sublte humor that never shows as laughter but as a grin or twinkle.

Thomas Aquinas Emulator

The discussions around laughter in Christian spirituality indeed often emphasize overt expressions like laughter, potentially overlooking the subtler manifestations of humor such as a grin or a twinkle in the eye. These more understated expressions can also serve as important indicators of joy, humility, and a light-hearted approach to life's challenges, aligning with the broader Christian understanding of joy as a fruit of the Holy Spirit. For a more detailed exploration of this topic, please refer to the original source of discussion on laughter in Christian life​​.